Distant Instantiation and Inheritance (1996 version)
11.1 The Basic Phenomena of Distant Instantiation
The varieties of instantiation we have studied up to now (excluding null instantiation and coinstantiation cases) all have a local character: the instantiations of the elements of a valence set are structurally connected to the relevant valence-bearing constituent as 'sister' in the usual case, as 'niece' in the case of the objects of null prepositions. Non-subject complements show up as sister to the lexical head of their phrase. In the case of subject instantiation, the VP carries the valence of its head verb, so the subject in the Spec-V construction is a sister to the VP, whose valence element it satisfies. In extraposition, the 'extraposed' constituent is a sister to the lexical verb and the it constituent is either a subject, a sister to the verb (in the object case) or a niece to the verb (in the case of prepositional objects). (Students of 220 in 1996 will not have covered those topics in 120 in 1995.) Coinstantiation, too, has a local character: the predicator which provides the coinstantiation is always the lexical head of the phrase immediately containing the complement needing subject instantiation.
There are also, however, instantiation relations which reach across an unlimited number of constituent boundaries. These are sometimes called long distance dependencies. We call the phenomenon distant instantiation, or equivalently, left isolation. (The term distant instantiation is to reflect the idea that the instantiating position can be at any structural distance from its predicator; the term left isolation may be less misleading, since in some cases the structure we have in mind is identical to the position of the subject in a Spec-V construction and therefore not 'distant' from the constituent whose valence it satisfies.) Another traditional name for the phenomenon in generative grammar is extraction, the image being that of 'extracting' a phrase such as what in example (1) from its normal position after bring and moving it to the front of the sentence.
(1) What do you think Pat told Lynn that someone persuaded Max to expect the postman to bring to the house?
In example (1) the word What is the left-isolated, extracted or distantly instantiated element. You should note that what does not take its place at the beginning of the sentence via a chain of coinstantiation links, as in the 'Equi' and 'Raising' sentences we have considered up to now. Rather, in sentence (1), what is linked by instantiation only to the object valence element of bring. This one-word phrase directly satisfies the object requirement of bring, which is structurally far from being a sister to it. Moreover, we can increase the constituent-boundary distance between the left isolated element and the predicator whose valence value it satisfies ad libitum, as illustrated in (2), where the italicized material has been inserted to increase that distance without loss of grammaticality.
(2) What do you think Pat told Lynn that someone said you believe me to have persuaded Max to expect the postman to bring to the house?
In examples (1) and (2) the left-isolated phrase is an interrogative word; but the construction is not limited to wh-words, as can be seen in (3)a, or even to phrases containing wh-words, as illustrated in (3)b.
(3)a Which of Shakespeare's plays do you think she said she would like to see?
b Troilus and Cressida, I don't think he would ever want to see.
In a later section we will deal with the formation of wh-phrases. For the time being we will concern ourselves with the Left Isolation (LI) construction itself.
11.2 The LI construction
11.2.1 Valence Embedding
11.2.2 The LI Construction Displayed and Explained
The Left Isolation construction forms a maximal verbal constituent by locating to the left of a maximal verbal constituent another constituent - the 'left-isolated' or 'extracted' constituent - whose synsem and rel values are unified with those of an element which is valence embedded in the right daughter. In examples (1) and (2) the left daughter of the LI construct consists of the word what and the right daughter consists of everything else. Also, in both of these examples, the left-isolated constituent does not satisfy a valence requirement of the main verb think, but rather of the verb bring, which is embedded several clauses under think.
In the diagram of the LI construction given as Figure 1, the notation inside the valence value of the right daughter says that (i) there is a valence element, call it v, which is embedded in the right daughter at an arbitrary depth, (ii) the rel and synsem values of v unify with the corresponding values of the left daughter (= the left isolated constituent) and (iii) that any constituent which is valence embedded in the right daughter and which itself valence embeds v carries the notation 'sealed -'.
The attributes 'sealed' and 'loc' are devoted to the expression of certain limitations of the LI construction. Although extraction can take place over an unlimited number of intervening consitituent of the right kind, there are certain kinds of constructs which, when they constitute what would be intervening constituents in the right daughter of an LI construct, render the resulting structure ungrammatical as an instance of LI. Otherwise put, extraction cannot take place from within certain kinds of structures. One example of a structure from which extraction cannot take place is the LI structure itself, a fact that is expressed by the notation 'sealed +' in its external syntax. We will consider several more examples in a later section. (Outside of the LI construction, it is only necessary that 'sealed +' structures, traditionally called 'islands', be marked for the 'sealed' attribute. Structures unmarked for the 'sealed' attribute will freely unify with the 'sealed -' requirement of the LI right daughter and its descendants, if any. fn. 1)
The 'sealed +' feature has the effect that nothing can be extracted from the constituent that it marks. If a constituent is marked with the attribute 'loc +' , which is to be read 'locally instantiated', that will mean that it is unextractable. We noted in connection with examples (8) and (9) in Chapter 8 that application of the Recipient construction blocks extraction of recipient non-subjects. We repeat those examples as (4) and (5) here.
(4) *Which spy do you think Agent 007 gave a parcel?
(Compare: Do you think Agent 007 gave Goldfinger a parcel?)
(5) *Which spy do you think a parcel was given?
(Compare: Do you think a parcel was given Goldfinger? Recall that A parcel was given Goldfinger is acceptable in `British' English.)
We may now prescribe that the Recipient construction marks such valence elements with the notation 'syn [loc +]'; this marking, together with the requirement that the LI constituent in Figure 1 specifies 'loc -', will prevent these valence elements from being distantly instantiated by the LI construction, and thus will block examples (4) and (5).
Using the 'extraction' terminology again, we can recapitulate what has been said about the two features concerned with restrictions on LI as follows. If a constituent has the feature 'sealed +', nothing can be extraced from it. If a constituent has the feature 'loc +', it cannot be extracted.
An LI construct is a full clause: it is marked 'srs +', which means that its subject requirement is internally satisfied. This subject may, however, either be realized (i) as the left daughter (Who did it?), (ii) within the right daughter (What did they do?), or (iii) within the right daughter by interpretation (...what to put it in). In case (i) the right daughter of the LI construct must be a VP (srs -); in case (ii) the right daughter must be a clause (srs +); in case (iii) the right daughter is marked srs+, in spite of the fact that it does not overtly contain an explicit subject, because it does not need its external context to satisfy its subject requirement.
The notation '[...#1[ ]...]' in the external semantics of the construction indicates that the semantics of the LI construct will contain (or possibly be the same as) the semantics of its right daughter. For example, in a sentence like That story I would never believe, the external semantics contains the proposition 'I would never believe that story' plus the information that 'that story' is topical.
As this chapter progresses we will see that the LI construction, as diagrammed in Figure 1, is really a family of constructions, or better an abstract construction whose properties are inherited by a number of more detailed constructions. What we mean by 'inheritance' of one construction by another construction will be made more precise presently. Our first illustration of this notion will be in connection with the structural pattern that goes by the name of Inversion.
11.3 Inversion
In the structure of English questions, we often find the word-order property known as subject-auxiliary inversion, or just plain inversion. In an inverted clause an auxiliary verb is followed by its subject, and that subject may be followed by additional constituents. In sentences (1) and (2) we found both inversion and the LI pattern, and it is easy to see that both LI and inversion are common in many questions.
Not all LI structures are questions, not all inverted structures are questions, not all LI structures are inverted, and not all inverted structures are LI structures. In short, the two patterns known as Inversion and Left Isolation are independently associated with various different constructions. In our discussion of inheritance, we will introduce a mechanism for describing and accounting for such interrelationships.
Example (6) illustrates both left isolation and inversion.
(6) Where did Lynn go?
In (6) the inverted clause did Lynn go constitutes the right daughter of an LI construct.
Examples (7) illustrate cases of left isolation which do not involve inversion.
(7) a Who stole the tarts?
b Raw oysters, you could never make me eat.
Examples (8) illustrate inversion in constructs which do not incorporate left isolation; the italicized portions represent the inverted (finite) auxiliary verb and subject.
(8) a Never will I leave you.
b So will she.
c Long may you prosper.
d Had I known, ...
The Inverted Clause (INV) construction is given in Figure 2.
An inversion construct is a clause (srs +), headed by an auxiliary verb, fn. 2,
which is followed by its subject, and perhaps by other complements. Since it is a kind of [cat v, max +], it can unify with the right daughter of the LI construction. The Kleene star marking the third interior box indicates that there can be zero or more constituents following the subject. In most ordinary sentences there will be something following the subject, but the 'zero' provision is to cover cases like those illustrated in (9) and (10). In (9) we have non-LI examples, and in (10) we have LI constructs in which the extracted element represents a predicate supported by the copula (= the auxiliary).
(9) a Has she?
b So do you.
(10) a Where is it?
b What kind of linguist is he?
11.4 Inheritance and Main Clause Yes-No Questions
In the case of many constructions, including several to be considered in this chapter, we can capture grammatical generalizations and at the same time achieve economy of presentation by noting that one construction may serve as a 'part' of another construction. At the end of the last section we referred vaguely to 'particular constructions which contain inverted clauses'. When we come to these constructions, we will be able to express them more economically by adopting a notation which refers to the INV construction, rather than by repeating all the information of the INV construction within the inverted clause constituent of the construction being defined.
For example, the syntax of one kind of main clause yes-no question (MCYNQ) is nothing more than that of the inverted clause (INV) construction, as illustrated in
(11) [[Did] [Pat] [remember to put the mayonnaise in the fridge]]?
We recall, however, that we need the INV construction independently of questions of any type for use in licensing sentences such as (6) and
(12) [Seldom] [[did] [Pat] [remember to put the mayonnaise in the fridge]].
In a MCYNQ like (11) the external syntax is simply that of the INV construction, while in the Neg(ative)-Adv(erb) construction, which licenses sentences such as (8)a and (12), the syntax of the right daughter is that of the INV construction. We will say that the relevant MCYNQ construction inherits the INV construction and that in the Neg-Adv construction, its right daughter inherits the INV construction. (We ignore the semantic aspects of these constructions for the moment to concentrate on their syntax.) Thus, semantics aside, the (Inverted) Matrix Y-N Question construction which licenses (11) can be represented as in Figure 3 and the Neg-Adv construction can be represented as in Figure 4.
In the statement of a construction, when we encounter in some box b the notation 'inherit X', we read that as indicating that all the information expressed in the construction named 'X' is in box b. For instance, all the information of the INV construction is contained in the right daughter of Neg-Adv. Everything else that we can add to a constituent marked 'inherit X' must unify with the construction named 'X' in that place. Thus, constituents (boxes) which contain an inheritance notation may also contain non-inherited information. For example, the construction we have been referring to as the (Inverted) MCYNQ never occurs embedded, as illustrated by the unacceptability of
(13) *I wonder whether did Pat put the mayonnaise in the fridge.
For this reason (among others) we need a way to distinguish main clauses from embedded clauses. Let us add the value for main[clause] to the possible values for the role attribute. So, while complement clauses display the role 'comp', main clauses carry the role 'main '. Then, in order to restrict inversion in questions to main clauses, we need only add the notation 'role main' to the external structure of the (Inverted) MCYNQ construction, thus:
Appearances to the contrary notwithstanding, an inheritance notation, such as 'inherit INV', does not represent an attribute value pair and does not denote part of the AVM of the constituent (box) in which it appears. The inheritance notation is, from a mechanical point of view, simply an abbreviatory shorthand because in place of writing, for example, 'inherit INV' we could have written in the appropriate box everything we wrote in the INV construction itself. That is, the revised version of the MCYNQ construction of Figure 5 is equivalent to the following, less perspicuous, representation (including the fact that we have not added below anything to indicate the semantics of interrogation). For present purposes the point that needs to be made is that the following representation of MCYNQ looks exactly like INV except for the addition of 'role main' to the external structure.
From the point of view of a computer program parsing a matrix yes-no question sentence, the inheritance notation (Figure 5) and the long winded notation (Figure 6) are equivalent, since they will accept exactly the same range of candidate sentences and assign them the same structures. But from a linguistic point of view, the inheritance notation says something more. It allows us to express the ways in which certain constructions are alike, and therefore to capture certain generalizations about the language. Thus, the nature of the structural relationship between the MCYNQ and Neg-Adv constructions is captured in the inheritance notation by our having posited the more abstract INV construction and indicating in the two more complex constructions that INV plays a role in each.
If we now take semantics and intonation into account, we will see that there is more than a single kind of MCYNQ and that the concept of inheritance can do much for us in sorting out and making clear the kinds of relationships that can hold among constructions.
Instead of uttering the sentence in (11), one can perform the same (or an
extremely similar) illocutionary act by uttering the sentence in (14), which
employs Spec-V syntax with a rising intonation contour (in contrast to the INV
syntax, with either rising or falling intonation, of 11). fn. 4
(14) Pat remembered to put the mayonnaise in the fridge? (Amazing!)
We are forced to notice, then, that there are two distinct MCYNQ constructions
illustrated by (11) and (14). Obviously we consider these two constructions
related, since we find it natural to give them the same name. This expression
in fact refers to three common properties of the two constructions: both are
main clause constructions (as against clauses that can occur embedded within
other clauses), both are questions, and semantically both may be used to
present a full proposition and request its acceptance or rejection (yes/no-type
questions) versus presenting a partial proposition and requesting its
completion (wh-type questions). We have already noted that the two
constructions differ in their overall syntactic form (INV) versus Spec-V and
in intonation; only the Spec-V type requires rising intonation, the INV type
permitting, but not requiring, this contour.
There is a further distinction to be made between the two constructions. This
is illustrated in example (15) and (16).
(15) a Did Pat take something from the fridge?
b Did Pat take anything from the fridge?
(16) a Pat took something from the fridge?
b *Pat took anything from the fridge?
The INV type question (15) can create what is called a negative polarity
environment, that is an environment in which words like anything, anyone,
any, and expressions like a red cent and lift a finger can
occur.fn. 5
(i) a *He likes me the least bit
(ii) a *He has any money
(iii) a *He got there until six
Although the phenomenon of polarity seems to be fundamentally semantic, it is
very difficult to say what the semantics of polarity is. Polarity is a
difficult and not well understood subject, both semantically and syntactically.
We will have a little more to say about it in a later chapter.
More precisely, the INV question (15) creates an environment which accepts
either positive or negative polarity items, while the Spec-V question (16)
creates an environment which accepts only positive polarity items.fn.
6
Our strategy is to formulate an abstract MCYNQ construction and then propose
two specific MCYNQ constructions, each of which inherits the abstract
construction. The former is given in Figure 7. This construction specifies
only a finite, main clause with 'yes-or-no' semantics. It does not commit
itself on inversion versus Spec-V form.
Figures 8 and 9 represent inverted and non-inverted MCYNQ
constructions, respectively. The inverted construction, shown in Figure 8,
inherits the abstract MCYNQ construction of Figure 7 and the INV construction
of Figure 2. Nothing more needs to be added to these specifications.
We have seen in this section that the mechanism of inheritance can be useful
in specifying similarities among constructions and in this way drawing
attention to syntactic generalizations. In discussing various related
constructions involving left isolation and some additional constructions with
which these interact, we will have frequent recourse to inheritance of one
construction by another. In particular, we will see that the LI construction
itself, like the INV construction and like the abstract MCYNQ constructions, is
inherited by several more specific constructions.
11.5 A Partial Classification of Finite Clauses
In order to give reasonable, though not exhaustive, coverage to the
phenomenon of LI, it is necesssary to discuss a fairly wide range of structures
which do not directly involve left isolation itself. There are two reasons for
this. First, a number of LI constructions either include or are included in
other (non-LI) constructions. Secondly, there are constraints on the operation
of the long distance dependency of the LI construction between the left
daughter and the valence element contained somewhere within the right daughter,
and to discuss these we must consider additional constructions.
In discussing examples (1) and (2) at the beginning of this chapter, we noted
that this dependency can exist across an unlimited number of clause boundaries.
But although there are certainly cases that conform to this generalization,
there are other cases in which left isolation is not possible. For example,
compare examples (17) and (18).
(17) Which rule did you say someone reported to the sergeant that Private
Schmallowitz had broken?
(18) *Which rule did the sergeant hear a report that Private Schmallowitz had
broken?
Even though the distance - measured in words, phrases or anything else -
between the left isolated element which rule and the predicator
broken, one of whose valence elements which rule satisfies, is
greater in sentence (17) than in (18), only the former is acceptable. It is
evidently something about the structure, not the length, of (18) that makes it
bad. Operation of the LI construction is constrained in a variety of ways, and
to discuss these we will have to consider a number of non-LI constructions
which interact with LI.
It will be convenient to classify finite clauses according to a tri-partite
division into (i) main clauses, (ii) argument or complement clauses and (iii)
clauses serving as modifiers. In the remainder of this section, we present a
classification of finite clause types and in section 5 we consider in greater
detail the specific constructions which license them.
11.5.1 Main Clauses
English contains a number of types of main clauses, several of which
inherit the LI construction. The only one we have considered in detail prior
to this chapter does not involve distant instantiation. It is the declarative
sentence type, which inherits the Spec-V construction and is illustrated in a
sentence like (19).
(19) She won the prize.
There are several types of main clause questions. In section 11.4 two types
of main clause yes-no questions were studied. One of these inherited Spec-V
and the other INV. Neither inherited LI.
Main-clause non-subject questions inherit both INV and LI, as seen in (20).
fn. 8
Main-clause subject questions inherit LI but not INV, as illustrated in
(21).
(21) Who won the prize?
There is another type of (non-question) main clause which inherits LI. This
is in fact an abstract syntactic type that contains semantically distinct
subtypes and thus deserves an abstract construction inherited by the specific
constructions licensing its subtypes. We may call this the Topic/Focus
construction. The topic version is illustrated in (22)a and the focus version
in (22)b.
(22)a The latter, he told me he would never agree to.
In (22)a we have chosen to employ an anaphoric element The latter for
the left-isolated constituent to emphasize that this kind of fronting syntax
can serve the rhetorical function of presenting an argument as already 'on the
floor' in the conversation. Contrastingly, in a sentence like (22)b the left
isolation of the element Operas can serve to indicate that it presents
the only 'new information' in the sentence, i.e., information not presupposed
to be present in the prior discourse. (There is a great deal more to be said
about the discoursse functions
of various topicalizing and focussing constructions than
will be mentioned here.)
There exists a variety of other kinds of main clauses of varying degrees of
productivity (versus idiomaticity). Without any claim to exhaustiveness and
with no attempt to decribe the special semantic/pragmatic values that attach to
their syntactic types, we mention three of these before going on to complement
clauses.
(23)a Leave my house!
Example (23)a illustrates an imperative sentence. The construction realized
by a sentence like (23)b may be called the Incredulity Construction and is
syntactically characterized as having a non-nominative subject and a main verb
in the bare stem form. The syntax of a sentence like (23)c - which will be
discussed in detail in a later chapter - takes more time to describe than we
have room for here. Notice, though, that it incorporates two instances of
inheritance of the LI construction: the more syntax is a left-isolated
complement of learn and the more of a party animal is a
left-isolated complement of become.
11.5.2 Complement Clauses
Verbs, nouns, and adjectives may contain valences which call for
clausal complements.
(24)a I think [that she won].
Clausal complements may also be questions.
(25)a I wonder [whether she won].
We can left-isolate a constituent of a non-question complement clause without
any problem.
(26) Who do you think (that) she told the news to?
It is generally maintained, however, that English
prohibits extraction from question complements.
Many examples
like (26) support this generalization.
(27) *Who do you wonder whether she told the news to?
It is possible, though, to find examples which seem to violate this
generalization.
(28) ?He's the guy who she's been wondering whether she should ask to the
prom.
In examples like (28), which many English speakers accept, who is a
left-isolated element which unifies with a valence element of ask; the
latter is inside the complement question whether she should ask to the prom.
Despite the existence of examples like (28), we will go along with the
orthodoxy according to which English prohibits extraction from embedded
questions.
We have seen that complement clauses can be subclassified as questions or
non-questions and that this subclassification has consequences with regard to
their behavior in left isolation contexts. In the examples we have considered
so far, each complement clause has been introduced with a special word, called
a complementizer, which serves just this purpose. In yes-no question
complements a complementizer, whether or if, is always necessary
(29)a,b, but (finite) non-question complement clauses can come either with or
without the complementizer that. fn.9
When a complement clause is introduced by a complementizer, its subject can
not be left-isolated.
(30) a Who do you think she likes?
The examples in (30) show that with a non-question complement, extraction of
the subject is blocked only when the clause is introduced by a complementizer.
With regard to question complements, the situation is apparently similar.
However much you accepted or failed to accept (28), we suspect you will find
(31) noticeably worse.
(31) *He's the guy who she's been wondering whether will ask her to the prom.
Example (31) appear to suffer because it left-isolates the subject of a
complement clause introduced by a complementizer - independently of the degree
to which it also suffers from left-isolating a constituent of an embedded
question.
In fact, these kinds of cumulative judgments of unacceptability have been used
to argue that the impossibility of left isolation of the subject of a
complement clause introduced by a complementizer is part of something more
general. It is possible that English prohibits extraction of the subject of
any clause that is introduced by a 'little word', whether or not the clause is
a complement and the 'little word' is a complementizer. It is hard to reach a
firm conclusion here because in most such clauses no extractions of any kind
are possible, and so one has to have recourse to judgments of cumulative
unacceptability of the kind we have just been considering. For example, left
isolation of any constituent of an adverbial subordinate clause tends to be
unacceptable.
(32) *What was Lynn frying the onions while Pat was chopping?
Many authors judge extraction of a subject from an
adverbial clause to sound even worse.
(33) *Who was Lynn frying the onions while was chopping the meat?
It is not implausible to conclude that (33) suffers both from violation of a
ban on left-isolation of any consituent of an adverbial clause and from
violation of a ban on left isolation of the subject of a clause introduced by a
'little word', including subordinating conjunctions such as while.
In theories that employ a notion of movement, a great deal of effort has
been devoted to explaining why the subject of an introduced complement
clause cannot be left isolated. In CG, this observation simply
follows from the fact that we have no constructions which license
structures consisting of a complementizer followed by a VP (i.e.,
an srs- constituent). You will recall in chapter 6 that we studied
constructions like those licensing that-clauses
and for-clauses, but none licensing
a structure consisting of a complementizer followed by a VP.
11.5.3 Relative Clauses
Most, but not all, relative clauses inherit the LI construction.
Relative clauses may first be subdivided into those which serve as
modifiers and those which do not. If you are familiar with only one of these
types, it is probably the former. Example (34)a contains a modifying relative
clause and example (34)b contains a non-modifying relative clause.
(34) a I have visited the town [where Pat used to live].
(You should not conclude from this pair of examples that any sequence of words
that forms a modifying relative clause also forms a non-modifying relative
clause, or conversely: who I know can only be of the modifying type;
what the dog ate can
only be of the non-modifying type.) Traditionally,
what we have called non-modifying relative clauses are called 'headless
relative clauses'. The name arises historically from the fact that this kind
of clause does not occur within a noun phrase headed by a lexical noun, since
such clauses don't modify nominal constituents; rather they function as noun
phrases by themselves. We will have more to say about non-modifying, or
headless, relative clauses below.
With regard to the semantic function of modifying relative clauses, we must
distinguish between restrictive and non-restrictive modification.
The distinction came up briefly with regard to modifying adjectives in Chapter
3, where we noted that proper nouns, since they denote unique individuals,
cannot be restrictively modified, although they can be non-restrictively
modified. (In (35)b the intended 'restrictive' interpretation is signalled by
the absence of a comma after Pat.)
(35) a I met a person who likes vodka and tonic.
There are three syntactic types of modifying relative clauses, as illustrated
in the following.
(36) a He bought the car which she hoped he'd buy.
We will call these types 'wh-relatives', 'that-relatives' and 'bare
relatives', respectively. All three types may be used for restrictive
modification, but only wh-relatives can serve as non-restrictive modifiers.
(37) a The car which my mother gave me is a 1983 Ford.
11.5.4 Non-Modifying or Headless Relative Clauses
Headless relatives differ in both external and internal semantics and
in external and internal syntax from modifying relatives. Considering external
function first, while modifying relatives modify nominal constituents, headless
relatives straightforwardly denote entities. They occur in places where we
expect a noun phrase. Example (34)b shows a headless relative fulfilling the
subject function. Examples (38)a,b show headless relatives fulfilling obj and
pobj functions, respectively.
(38) a I found what I was looking for.
With respect to their internal syntax, headless relatives can be
subclassified into the -ever type and the ordinary type (illustrated in
38). Examples (39)a,b present the -ever versions of examples (38)a,b.
(39) a I found whatever I was looking for.
11.5.5 Headless Relatives versus Embedded Questions
The syntax of non-ever headless relatives is in many cases identical to
that of embedded questions and the two are easy to confuse. Thus, in some
contexts a given string of words which can be interpreted as a headless
relative may also be interpreted as an embedded question.
The verb wonder takes only an embedded question as a complement, while
a verb like cook does not accept any sort of propositional complement,
including question complements. Thus the italicized phrase in (40)a is
necessarily an embedded question while that in (40)b is necessarily a headless
relative.
(40) a I wonder what he cooked.
A common rule-of-thumb for distinguishing headless relatives from complement
questions pairs the possibility of substituting a wh-ever form for the
simple wh-word in the case of headless relatives (only) with the possibility of
adding the anaphoric element else only to the embedded question, thus:
(41) a I wonder what else he cooked.
Some predicators take either sort of complement. The verb know, for
example, allows both NP objects (know the facts ) and embedded
question complements (know how to do it ). By using know
as both the root and the complement verb, we can get an ambiguity of
interpretation of the complement as either headless relative or embedded
question. Examples (42) illustrate this with the -ever
versus else test.
(42) a I know whatever Syd knows.
So a sentence like
(43) I know what he knows.
can be interpreted along the lines of either (42)a (headless relative) or (42)b
(embedded question).
Having briefly subclassified some of the major varieties of finite clauses, we
turn now to the constructions which license these clauses. Our attention will
be focussed upon those constructions which inherit or which interact with
left isolation.
11.6 Main Clause Constructions
An ordinary declarative sentence is, syntactically speaking, simply a
Spec-V construct which is marked as a finite main clause.
11.6.1 MCYNQs
MCYNQ constructions were treated in 11.4. We simply recall here that
there were two types, one having the syntax of INV and the other the syntax of
Spec-V, with differing intonation possibilities and different constraints on
polarity items.
11.6.2 Main Clause Wh Questions
Our having named the main clause wh question constructions exemplified in (21)
and (22) 'non-subject' and 'subject', respectively, requires some
amplification. 'Subject' here refers only to the subject of the right daughter
of the LI construct itself, not to the subject of any clause embedded within
the right daughter of the LI construct. Thus, repeating (21) and (22) for
convenience, we see that an example such as (44)a,b in which either an embedded
subject or an embedded non-subject is extracted has, like (21), inversion in
the right daughter.
(21) What did she win?
(22) Who won the prize?
(44) a What do you think she won?
Non-subject main clause wh questions are, thus, those in which the
left-isolated element unifies with any valence element of any predicator of the
right daughter except for the subject requirement of the main verb of the right
daughter.
11.6.3 Main Clause Subject Wh Questions
A main clause subject wh question, such as (22), inherits both the LI and
Spec-V constructions. The left-isolated, wh phrase and the subject are the
same constituent! There is no inversion.
11.6.4 Topicalization and Related Constructions
The Topic/Focus construction raises certain questions regarding how the data
should be construed. The question is whether, or rather under what conditions,
this construction permits distant instantiation properly so-called. That is,
when the left-isolated element does not unify with a valence requirement of the
main verb, whether or not the left isolation is possible appears to depend on
the meaning of the intervening clause(s). Examples (45)a,b seem to be okay
with everyone.
(45)a Braised cockroach I would never eat.
Example (45)a exemplifies extraction from a main clause, while (45)b
represents extraction from an embedded clause (distant instantiation). But
whereas any sentence like (45)a will be judged fine, many sentences of the
(45)b type may be judged questionable.
(46) *Braised cockroach Lynn bet Pat would never eat.
Many would judge sentence (46) ungrammatical,
but accept (47).
(47) ?Braised cockroach I'll bet I would never eat.
Sentences (46) and (47) have the same structure; in fact the intervening verb
bet is the same in both. What might make the difference is that I'll
bet can be considered almost semantically empty in (47). The expression
I'll bet often functions as a mild hedge on a prediction: the sentences
Pat is going to be late and I'll bet Pat is going to be late
probably do not differ in truth conditions (on one reading of I'll bet ).
Lynn bet in (46) is, however not subject to this
kind of interpretation. Since it is likely that complex aspects of
interpretation affect judgments of acceptability in these cases, we tentatively
conclude that the grammar itself treats topic/focus constructions as allowing
left isolation of all embedded arguments. We propose then, that what makes a
sentence like (46) hard to accept is not part of English grammar per se, but
rather must ultimately be explained by the mechanisms according to which
certain aspects of utterances relating to notions such as topic and focus are
processed. The topic/focus constructions are most suited to conversation, and
it may simply be that cognitively complex sentences sound unnatural in ordinary
conversation.
Although Topic and Focus versions of this construction differ with regard to
the differences in the semantics of topics and foci,
they all have in common a semantic restriction: the left isolated element must
be semantically contentful. Null elements cannot be topicalized as illustrated
by the acceptable passivization in (48)a and the unacceptable topicalization in
(48)b of the null element and the acceptable topicalization of the non-null
element in (48)c.
(48) a It was expected to rain.
Idiom chunks, similarly, appear more readily in initial position as passive
subjects than as topics (or foci).
(49) a Unfair advantage was taken of his customers by Karl Cheating.
This constraint on the Topic/Focus construction - that the first element must
be semantically contentfull - is reflected by the
notation 'rel ~[theta null]' (negation in this text being
symbolized by '~' and greek letters being written out) on
the left daughter in Figure 13.
Complement clauses can be subclassified according to whether or not they are
questions and according to whether or not they are introduced by a
complementizer.
11.7.1 Introduced Complement Clauses
We consider first the case of complement clauses introduced by a
complementizer. For such clauses we need only a single construction, as we can
let the nature of the complementizer determine whether the introduced clause is
a question.
The lexical complementizer that carries the notation 'mood
declarative', while whether and if carry 'mood interrogative'.
This feature is copied into the semantics of the introduced clause and there
determines whether or not the introduced clause is interpreted as a question.
This construction will license the italicized parts of examples like
(50) a I believe that Pat ate the pizza.
Since this construction requires that its right daughter be a Spec-V
constituent and since the Spec-V construction requires internal instantiation
of the subject, left isolation of the subject of the italicized clause in each
of the above cases is impossible, as indicated in
(51) a *Who do you believe that ate the pizza?
While extraction is possible from the complements of verbs and adjectives, as
in (52)a,b, or from the prepositional complements of nouns, as in (52)d,f,
extraction is not possible from clausal complements of nouns, as in (53).
(52) a What does Pat believe that Lynn wrote in the notebook?
(53) *What does Pat resent the fact that Lynn wrote in the notebook?
Because of the clear acceptability of (51)a,b, we cannot attribute the
unacceptability of a sentence like (52) to sealing of the italicized complement
clause. Because of the acceptability of (51)d and (51)f, we cannot say that
all complex NPs are sealed. A brute-force solution is to stipulate that noun
phrases containing clausal complements are sealed.
11.7.2 Bare Complement Clauses
Complement clauses, either questions or non-questions, can also occur
without complementizers. In this case, however, two separate constructions are
required. Whether or not the complement clause is interpereted as a question
cannot be determined by the complementizer, since there is none. Further, the
internal syntax of bare question complements differs from that of bare
non-question complements.
Bare question complements take the form of wh-marked LI structures.
(54) a I wonder who gave it to her.
We can represent the Bare Complement Question construction, again
ignoring semantics, as follows.
The fact that bare question complements are realized as LI structures
accounts for the fact that no element of such a structure can be left-isolated.
Compare the following to (54)a,b,c (and to main clause double questions like
Which toy will you give to which child?).
(55)a *Which toy do you wonder who gave to the child?
11.7.3 Bare Non-Question Complements
Bare non-question (declarative) complements are exemplified by
sentences like
(56) Pat thinks Lynn likes potato chips.
Unlike bare question complements and both types of introduced complements,
bare non-question complements allow distant instantiation of their subjects
(that is the subject of their main verb). Thus,
(57) Who does Pat think likes potato chips?
These complements are not LI structures, as are bare complement questions, and
they are also not specified to be clauses (srs +), as introduced complements
are. Bare non-question complements are unspecified with respect to the srs
attribute. They are not inverted and will appear either as VPs (57) or as
Spec-Vs (56).
We discuss in turn the constructions for the modifying types of
relative clause: wh, that, and bare and then for the non-modifying
(headless) types: plain and -ever.
11.8.1 Modifying Relative Clause Constructions
A modifier is like a predicator in the respect that both have an unsatisfied
valence element. We might say that while a modifier and a predicator are
dedicated to doing different jobs (predication versus modification), each
requires that it combine with another constituent (the one described in its
unsatisfied valence element) in order to do its own job.
fn. 10
(i) A spectator
We attribute the difference in semantics observed in (ii) versus (iii), not to
distinct predicative and modifying lexical entries scream, but rather to
a difference between modificational and predicational constructions. Noun
modifiers are not the only kind of modifiers that exist. There are also
predicate modifiers, which map predicates to predicates (e.g. 'fast' to 'very
fast'), and other types as well. A modifier always maps an element of a given
semantic type to another element of the same semantic type. A predicate never
does this.
(58) a [a man] who I met in Kabul
In (58)a the meaning of who will unify with the unsatisfied valence
element of the relative clause who I met in Kabul and thence unify with
the meaning of the modified noun man. In (58)b the meaning of the left
isolated phrase whose sister does not in its entirely unify with the
external valence element of the construct whose sister I met in Kabul
and thence with the head noun man. Rather a part of the meaning of
whose sister, (the 'who' part), does this. Figure 17 depicts the wh
modifying relative clause construction.
In Figure 17 we may note first that a new phrasal role, modifier
(mdfr), has been assigned to the construction. We may imagine in retrospect
that in the Modified Nominal Construction of Chapter 3, and in all other
modificational constructions, fn. 11
(59) *a rock who fell on my head
is peculiar because the information 'human' contained in who clashes
with what we know about rocks.
11.8.1.1 That -Relatives
The that-relative relative construction is exactly like the wh-relative
except that the word that occurs as the sole element of the left
daughter.
The construction in Figure 18 specifies the word that to be the
whole of the left-isolated constituent. Thus, we can have relative-including
structures like (60)a,b,c but not like (60)d.
(60) a the guy that we were talking about.
We think of the word that in this construction as a special
kind of relative pronoun. It has the semantics of a wh-pronoun (whatever that
may be); it occurs only in this construction; and it necesarily constitutes the
whole of the left isolated element in the construction. fn 12 12 This is not the only possible analysis
of that-relatives.
Another will be considered later.
11.8.1.2 Some Baffling Mysteries Involving Special Head Nouns
There are a number of puzzling cases in which a head noun accepts a
relative clause with a wh-word which seems redundant with part of the meaning
of the noun (e.g., 'time' or 'place') and also accepts either a that
relative or a bare relative, but does not accept a relative with the wh-word
which, unless a preposition is included to carry the temporal- or
spatial-location meaning. In examples (61) the word day
incorporates the idea of a location in time redundantly with the word when.
In examples (62) the word place incorporates the notion of location
in space redundantly with the word where. This kind of head noun is
happy with semantically redundant relative introducers (when, where) and
also with that and bare relatives. But, as noted, a preposition is
required with the relative pronoun which.
(61) a the day when Pat and Lynn met.
(62) a the place where Pat and Lynn met.
Way and reason as head nouns prohibit stranded prepositions,
contrasting in this respect with the f examples in the two preceeding sets.
(63) a the way in which she convinced him.
(65) a the reason that she prepared the speech so carefully.
Examples (61-65) repesent the tip of an iceberg of mysteries surrounding
interactions between the members of a small set of head nouns, whose semantics
is to some degree redundant with that of a relative pronoun (time, place,...),
and certain finicky details of the form of allowable relative clauses.
11.8.1.2 Bare Relative Clause Constructions
Bare relatives behave somehat, but not entirely, like other modifying
relatives. In particular, like other modifying relatives they illustrate the
phenomenon of long distance dependency, which up to now we have spoken of as
restricted to the LI construction.
(66) a the man you thought I said she had spoken about.
It is important to notice, however, that the long distance dependency in (66)a
does not relate two constituents within the relative clause. There is a long
distance dependency in (66)a between a valence element of about and the
head noun man, but there is no constituent of the relative clause in
(66)a which participates in this dependency as do the that and
who constituents in (66)b,c. We cannot, therefore say that the bare
relative construction inherits LI. There is nothing in bare relatives to fill
the left daughter of an LI structure. We will consequently have to devise
another means to capture the long distance dependency in (66)a.
Bare relatives behave differently from the other modifying relatives in a
second way. In bare relatives the 'extracted' valence element, i.e., the one
that ends up dependent upon the head noun to which the relative clause is
attached, cannot be the subject of the relative clause. fn. 13
(67)a *The man thought I said we were raising our prices refused to
renew his subscription.
In bare relatives the subject is always instantiated internally, in its normal
position. In both wh-relatives and that relatives, the subject is also
always instantiated internally, but this comes about differently. In the bare
relative case we have an ordinary Spec-V structure with the subject at home.
In the wh and that cases we find either (a) the left-isolate daughter
unified with a non-subject and the subject instantiated within the right
daughter or (b) the subject occupying the left-isolate daughter and marked 'loc
-'. Thus, bare relatives have a Spec-V structure, not an LI structure, but
they share with the LI relatives the possibility for an embedded argument to be
associated with the head noun, creating a long-distance dependency. So, bare
relatives are Spec-V structures whose right daughters share with the right
daughters of LI relatives (i.e., wh and that relatives) the property
that some valence element contained within them - not necessarily one belonging
to the main predicate of the relative clause - becomes an external valence
element. The following diagram of the bare relative construction incorporates
these properties.
The above diagram is like rather like that of the other modifying relative
clauses except that the left daughter is the subject and cannot function as the
'loc -' element. The overall structure is that of a Spec-V construct rather
than an LI construct. However, the part of the LI construction which makes
possible long distance instantiation is written into the bare relative
construction (in the form of the unlimited number of optional unsealed
constituents dominated by the right daughter and dominating the predicator
governing the externally satisfied valence element).
It was mentioned in a note earlier that a second analysis of
that-relatives is possible. This analysis treats the that of
that-relatives, not as a special kind of relative pronoun, but as a
special use of the complementizer that. Under such an analysis the
that-relative construction is more directly related to the bare
relatives than to the wh relatives. That appears as a left daughter
complementizer in a construction whose right daughter is a bare relative and
whose external structure inherits everything from its right daughter. A
version of such a construction is given in Figure 20.
Ordinary, non-ever, headless relatives have a syntactic shape
that often allows them to be confused with complement questions. The meaning
of a headless relative is, however, different from that of an embedded
question. Also, ordinary headless relatives have an internal syntactic
property that distinguishes them as a subclass of the class of structures that
can appear in environments where either a headless relative or an embedded
question is permitted, as after the verb discover. The following
example,
(68) She discovered what he had hidden,.
is ambiguous between an embedded question reading, in which she found out the
identity of the hidden object, and a headless relative reading, in which she
found the hidden object. However, the examples in (69) are not ambiguous in
this (or any other) way. They must each be interpreted as an embedded
question, not as a headless relative.
(69) a She discovered which one he had hidden.
Compare the examples in (70), each of which presents an environment which does
not accept an embedded question.
(70) a *She picked up which one he had hidden.
The lexical makeup of the left daughter of an ordinary headless
relative must consist exclusively of one of the words what, where, when, how
or why. Multi-word wh-phrases are not possible, nor are those
consisting of the words whose or which, which would require an
interpretation in which some nominal element is anaphorically reconstructed
('whose key', 'which key').
The majority of the actual tokens of headless relatives one encounters begin
with what, but a few verbs allow as complements headless relatives which
begin with the other wh-words listed. For example, the verbs admire and
deplore require explicit objects.
(71) a *I admire.
From this fact it follows that in (72) the italicized phrases are complements,
not adverbial clauses.
(72) a I admire what he did but I deplore why he did it.
Examples (73) show that the clauses italicized in (72) must be headless
relatives and not embedded questions (which agrees with our intuitions
regarding their meanings).
(73) a *I deplore why else he did it.
Examples (74)a,b illustrate headless relatives in where and
when.
(74) a Did you see where it went?.
(Headless relatives in who, are also marginally possible, but
have a tightly restricted distribution: I like who he married is
fine but *I wrestled who he married, *Who he married is coming to dinner,
and *He gave who he married a lovely ring are bizarre. Who
steals my purse steals trash is a remembered line from the earlier English
of Shakespeare and Can I help who's next? appears to be a recent
idiomatic innovation.)
In semantic type, headless relatives are arguments, not modifiers. They
appear in such grammatical functions as subj, obj, pobj, etc. They generally
appear where one might expect a NP, for example as the object of a predicator
such as pick up (compare examples 70). Briefly, and with several
oversimplifications, we can make the following contrast. An expression which
is unambiguously a modifying relative because of its syntactic structure, such
as
(75) whose book Pat borrowed
cannot be used to refer to an entity. It can only participate in referring to
something when it is combined with an expression which already has the
potential to refer. The entity that gets referred to by the combination of
expressions is one that satisfies the meanings of each expression. (This is an
oversimplification.) Thus,
(76) the student
can refer to an entity, and
(77) the student whose book Pat borrowed
refers to an entity x such that (i) x is a student and (ii) Pat borrowed x's
book.
A headless relative, on the other hand, can refer to an entity and can perform
most of the other semantic functions that garden variety NPs do. Hence we are
not surprised to find that headless relatives occur in environments where
ordinary NPs are welcome. Example (78) represents a construct which can't be a
modifying relative, because what cannot introduce a modifying
relative.
(78) what Pat had hidden behind the couch
An expression like (78) can be used directly to refer to an entity x such that
Pat hid x behind the couch.
(79) Lynn stepped on what Pat had hidden behind the couch.
In formulating the Headless Relative Clause construction, we must account for
the fact that headless relatives behave externally as noun phrases despite the
fact that they are internally organized by LI, which licenses a verbal
constituent according to the formulation of Figure 1. We might do this in
either of two ways. The first, and probably preferable, way involves slightly
redoing the LI construction of Figure 1 in such a way that syntactic category
is unspecified, rather than specified as 'v', in the external structure. Then
all the kinds of LI structures that we have treated up to now would inherit a
second 'Verbal LI' construction, which would itself inherit LI and simply add
'cat v' and 'srs +'. That would leave the more abstract LI unspecified for
category and thus available to be inherited by the headless relative
construction of Figure 21. (In our diagrammatic representation of the headless
relative construction (Figure 21), the external semantics value is intended to
be no more than suggestive of a serious treatment of the semantics of the
construction.)
We will not show anything in our representation of the -ever headless
relative construction to deal with its (sometime) semantic differences from the
ordinary headless relative construction beyond the purely mnemonic and
unexplanatory notation 'ever +'.
Syntactically, -ever relatives differ from ordinary headless relatives
in that they permit the full range of possible wh-phrases as left-isolate
daughter.
(80) a Whatever it was made of must have been expensive.
Consequently, in the representation of the -ever relative construction,
there is no 'lex +' notation in the syn value of the left daughter.
Essentially the same alternative analyses represented in Figures 21 and 21a for
ordinary headless relatives are possible for -ever headless relatives.
Since all headless relative constructions inherit LI, we have accounted for the
fact that all headless relatives are islands.
11.9 'What the ... !'
Frequently, but by no means always, a wh-phrase can contain, directly
following the wh-word, an exclamatory expression like the heck, the
daylights, the devil, in heaven's name, in (the) blue blazes, in tarnation,
and so on. But what on earth are we to make of the distribution of
wh-exclamations exemplified in (81)?
(81) a Who the devil cares? [main clause question]
The contrast in acceptability between f and g may perhaps be explained as a
register clash in g. Wh-exclamations appear to be characteristic of casual
speech, while pied-piping characterizes writing, or speech which emulates
written style. In a sentence which reaches for a humorous effect through a
mixture of written and casual registers (such as the final sentence of the
preceding paragraph), wh-exclamations with pied-piping seem more at home.
(82) To what on earth may we attribute the distribution illustrated in (81)?
Assuming we have accounted for the unacceptability of g, we are left with the
observation that wh-exclamations are acceptable in questions, either root (81)a
or embedded (b,f) and in ever-relatives (c), but not elsewhere. If we
could find some factor common to questions and -ever-relatives, but
lacking elsewhere, that would provide the desired explanation of the
distribution.
11.10 Constraints on Left Isolation
... to be continued...
4 In this section we do not attempt to analyze either intonational
or semantic phenomena with the subtlety that would be necessary to satisfy a
phonologist or semanticist but merely to make sufficient distinctions in these
domains to be able to sort out the correlated syntactic facts.
5 Negation, if , most questions, and a variety of other
circumstances create so-called negative polarity environments, that is,
environments in which certain forms, called negative polarity items, can occur.
The latter include the word any and words prefixed by any-,
expressions (many of them idiomatic) indicating a minimal or zero amount of
something (the least bit, the slightest intention, a red cent ) and a
bewildering collection of other items, such as until in a sentence like
(iii).
b He doesn't like me the least bit
b If he has any money, he'll buy it
b I doubt he got there until six
6 The representation of polarity in unificational terms - apart from
the questions regarding its essential nature raised in the previous note -
itself poses technical problems of a sort which we will not pursue here. Our
formal statements of the various MCYNQ constructions will therefore overlook
the polarity issue.
8 By 'subject questions' and 'non-subject questions' we mean
questions in which a subject or a non-subject, respectively, is questioned by
means of a left-isolated wh-word or wh-phrase. We therefore don't need to
mention each time that these are wh questions.
(20) What did she win?
b [I like to go to plays and movies.] Operas, I'm unable to work up much
enthusiasm for.
b Him get into med school?!
c The more syntax you learn the more of a party animal you become.
b I am entertaining the thought [that she won].
c I am aware [that she won].
b I am entertaining the question [whether she won].
c I am uncertain [whether she won].
9 Some dialects of English allow embedded questions with
inversion and without a complementizer: I wonder did she win, I
wonder who did she see. We exclude these dialects from consideration to
keep the array of data manageable.
(29) a *I wonder she won.
b *the question she won.
c I think (that) she won.
d I am sure (that) she won.
b Who do you think likes her?
c Who do you think that she likes?
d *Who do you think that likes her?
b [Where Pat used to live] was a one-horse town.
b *I met Pat who likes vodka and tonic.
c I met Pat, who likes vodka and tonic.
b He bought the car that she hoped he'd buy.
c He bought the car she hoped he'd buy.
b *My car, that my mother gave me, is a 1983 Ford.
c *My car, my mother gave me, is a 1983 Ford.
b She talks about what she likes.
b She talks about whatever she likes.
b I ate what he cooked.
b *I wonder whatever he cooked.
c I ate whatever he cooked.
d *I ate what else he cooked.
b I know what else Syd knows.
b Who do you think won the prize?
b Braised cockroach I don't believe I would ever eat.
b *It they expected to rain.
c Pat they expected to cooperate.
b *Unfair advantage Karl Cheating took of his customers.
b I wonder whether/if Pat ate the pizza.
c I am happy that Pat ate the Pizza.
d I am uncertain whether/if Pat ate the pizza.
e The fact that Pat ate the pizza is important.
f The question whether Pat ate the pizza is unimportant.
b *Who do you wonder whether ate the pizza?
c *Who are you happy that ate the pizza?
d * Who are you uncertain whether ate the pizza?
e *Who is the fact that ate the pizza important?
f *Who is the question whether ate the pizza unimportant?
b What is Pat sorry that Lynn wrote in the notebook?
c The prophet witnessed the destruction of the Roman Empire
d Which empire did the prophet witness the destruction of?
e This is the lid to the pickle jar.
f Which jar is this the lid to?
b I wonder what he gave to her .
c I wonder why he gave it to her
b *Which child do you wonder which toy I gave to?
c *Which toy do you wonder why I gave to the child?
10 While predicators map (representations of) entities to
propositions or events, modifiers map (representations of) entities to
(representations of) entities. Thus, (i) denotes a human being; the
predication (ii) denotes an event or proposition, and the modifications
(iii)a,b again denote human beings.
(ii) A spectator screamed.
(iii) a A screaming spectator
b A spectator who was screaming
In the wh type modifing relative clause construction, the unsatisfied valence
element unifies with all (58)a or part (58)b of the left isolated
constituent.
b [a man] whose sister I met in Kabul
11 For example, those in which
adverbs modify APs or VPs.
the modifer constituent bears this role. Any semantic information contained in
the wh-word becomes part of the sem value of the external valence element, it
has to unify with the semantics of the head nominal that the relative clause
modifies. Thus,
b the guy whom we were talking about.
c the guy about whom we were talking.
d *the guy about that we were talking.
Notice that the process of inheritance is begining to do a lot of labor-saving
work for us. As we develop a hierarchy of inheritance, we see first that wh
modifying relatives inherit a lot of their structure from LI and then that
that- relatives inherit all of this structure and more from wh modifying
relatives. We are not merely saving ink by using the device of inheritance but
also displaying generalizations regarding relations of similarity among
constructions.
b the day that Pat and Lynn met.
c the day Pat and Lynn met.
d the day on which Pat and Lynn met.
e the day Pat and Lynn met on.
f *the day which Pat and Lynn met.
b the place that Pat and Lynn met.
c the place Pat and Lynn met.
d the place at which Pat and Lynn met.
e the place Pat and Lynn met at.
f *the place which Pat and Lynn met.
b *the way she convinced him in.
c the reason for which she prepare the speech so carefully.
d *the reason which she prepared the speech so carefully for.
These special head nouns also accept both that and bare relatives.
(64) a the way that she convinced him.
b the way she convinced him.
b the reason she prepared the speech so carefully.
b the man that you thought I said she had spoken about.
c the man who you thought I said she had spoken about.
13 This property of bare relatives was not present in all earlier
stages of English. In such attested modern English sentences as We had a
friend of mine from Norway was staying here, Knud Lambrecht has argued that
was staying here does not consitute a relative clause. Rather what
appears in this sentence to be a bare relative with an externally realized
subject is in fact a complement of a specialized lexeme have with a
particular presentational semantics.
Compare the unacceptability of (67)a with the acceptability of (67)b,c.
b The man who thought I said we were raising our prices refused
to renew his subscription.
c The man that thought I said we were raising our prices refused
to renew his subscription.
b She discovered which he had hidden.
c She discovered whose key he had hidden.
d She discovered whose he had hidden.
b *She picked up which he had hidden.
c *She picked up whose key he had hidden.
d *She picked up whose he had hidden.
b *I deplore.
b I deplore what he did but I admire how he did it.
b *I admire how else he did it.
b I remember when a coke cost a nickel.
b *Which material it was made of must have been expensive.
c Whoever's dogs have been in my garden had better watch out.
d *Whose dogs have been in my garden had better watch out.
b I can't imagine who on earth would care [complement
question]
c Whoever the heck cares about such a thing ought to have
their head examined [-ever headless relative]
d *I met someone who the devil cares about it [modifying
relative]
e *You found what in
blue blazes? [ordinary headless relative]
f Who the hell's car did you get here in?
J[preposition stranding(main clause question)]
g *In who the hell's car did you get
here? [pied-piping (main clause question)]