Logical conjunction

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Logical conjunction
AND
Venn diagram of Logical conjunction
Definition
Truth table
Logic gateAND ANSI.svg
Normal forms
Disjunctive
Conjunctive
Zhegalkin polynomial
Post's lattices
0-preservingyes
1-preservingyes
Monotoneno
Affineno
Self-dualyes
Venn diagram of

In logic, mathematics and linguistics, And (∧) is the truth-functional operator of logical conjunction; the and of a set of operands is true if and only if all of its operands are true. The logical connective that represents this operator is typically written as or .

is true only if is true and is true.

An operand of a conjunction is a conjunct.

The term "logical conjunction" is also used for the greatest lower bound in lattice theory.

Related concepts in other fields are:

Notation[edit]

And is usually denoted by an infix operator: in mathematics and logic, it is denoted by , & or × ; in electronics, ; and in programming languages, &, &&, or and. In Jan Łukasiewicz's prefix notation for logic, the operator is K, for Polish koniunkcja.[1]

Definition[edit]

Logical conjunction is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if and only if both of its operands are true.

The conjunctive identity is 1, which is to say that AND-ing an expression with 1 will never change the value of the expression. In keeping with the concept of vacuous truth, when conjunction is defined as an operator or function of arbitrary arity, the empty conjunction (AND-ing over an empty set of operands) is often defined as having the result 1.

Truth table[edit]

Conjunctions of the arguments on the left — The true bits form a Sierpinski triangle.

The truth table of :

T T T
T F F
F T F
F F F

Defined by other operators[edit]

In systems where logical conjunction is not a primitive, it may be defined as[2]

Introduction and elimination rules[edit]

As a rule of inference, conjunction Introduction is a classically valid, simple argument form. The argument form has two premises, A and B. Intuitively, it permits the inference of their conjunction.

A,
B.
Therefore, A and B.

or in logical operator notation:

Here is an example of an argument that fits the form conjunction introduction:

Bob likes apples.
Bob likes oranges.
Therefore, Bob likes apples and oranges.

Conjunction elimination is another classically valid, simple argument form. Intuitively, it permits the inference from any conjunction of either element of that conjunction.

A and B.
Therefore, A.

...or alternately,

A and B.
Therefore, B.

In logical operator notation:

...or alternately,

Properties[edit]

commutativity: yes

        
Venn0001.svg          Venn0001.svg

associativity: yes

        
Venn 0101 0101.svg Venn 0000 0011.svg          Venn 0000 0001.svg          Venn 0001 0001.svg Venn 0000 1111.svg

distributivity: with various operations, especially with or

        
Venn 0101 0101.svg Venn 0011 1111.svg          Venn 0001 0101.svg          Venn 0001 0001.svg Venn 0000 0101.svg

idempotency: yes

        
Venn01.svg Venn01.svg          Venn01.svg

monotonicity: yes

        
Venn 1011 1011.svg          Venn 1111 1011.svg          Venn 0000 0101.svg Venn 0000 0011.svg

truth-preserving: yes
When all inputs are true, the output is true.

        
Venn0001.svg          Venn0001.svg
(to be tested)

falsehood-preserving: yes
When all inputs are false, the output is false.

        
Venn0001.svg          Venn0111.svg
(to be tested)

Walsh spectrum: (1,-1,-1,1)

Nonlinearity: 1 (the function is bent)

If using binary values for true (1) and false (0), then logical conjunction works exactly like normal arithmetic multiplication.

Applications in computer engineering[edit]

In high-level computer programming and digital electronics, logical conjunction is commonly represented by an infix operator, usually as a keyword such as "AND", an algebraic multiplication, or the ampersand symbol "&". Many languages also provide short-circuit control structures corresponding to logical conjunction.

Logical conjunction is often used for bitwise operations, where 0 corresponds to false and 1 to true:

  • 0 AND 0  =  0,
  • 0 AND 1  =  0,
  • 1 AND 0  =  0,
  • 1 AND 1  =  1.

The operation can also be applied to two binary words viewed as bitstrings of equal length, by taking the bitwise AND of each pair of bits at corresponding positions. For example:

  • 11000110 AND 10100011  =  10000010.

This can be used to select part of a bitstring using a bit mask. For example, 10011101 AND 00001000  =  00001000 extracts the fifth bit of an 8-bit bitstring.

In computer networking, bit masks are used to derive the network address of a subnet within an existing network from a given IP address, by ANDing the IP address and the subnet mask.

Logical conjunction "AND" is also used in SQL operations to form database queries.

The Curry–Howard correspondence relates logical conjunction to product types.

Set-theoretic correspondence[edit]

The membership of an element of an intersection set in set theory is defined in terms of a logical conjunction: xAB if and only if (xA) ∧ (xB). Through this correspondence, set-theoretic intersection shares several properties with logical conjunction, such as associativity, commutativity, and idempotence.

Natural language[edit]

As with other notions formalized in mathematical logic, the logical conjunction and is related to, but not the same as, the grammatical conjunction and in natural languages.

English "and" has properties not captured by logical conjunction. For example, "and" sometimes implies order. For example, "They got married and had a child" in common discourse means that the marriage came before the child. The word "and" can also imply a partition of a thing into parts, as "The American flag is red, white, and blue." Here it is not meant that the flag is at once red, white, and blue, but rather that it has a part of each color.

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Józef Maria Bocheński (1959), A Précis of Mathematical Logic, translated by Otto Bird from the French and German editions, Dordrecht, North Holland: D. Reidel, passim.
  2. ^ Smith, Peter. "Types of proof system" (PDF). p. 4.

External links[edit]