Leibniz's gap

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Leibniz's gap is a philosophy of mind term that is used to refer to the problem that thoughts cannot be observed or perceived solely by examining brain properties, events, and processes. Here the word 'gap' is a metaphor of a subquestion regarding the mind-body problem that allegedly must be answered in order to reach a more profound understanding of consciousness and emergence. A theory that could correlate brain phenomena with psychological phenomena would "bridge the gap."

The term Leibniz's gap was coined by Robert Cummins[1][2] and was named after Gottfried Leibniz who first presented the problem in his work The Monadology in 1714. Leibniz's passage describing the gap goes as follows:

The problem according to Leibniz is that there is a gap between concepts of modern neuroscience and those that we use to describe the brain such as "thought," "feeling," and "perception". This means that the physical observation of the brain yields data in the wrong vocabulary even if we are convinced that the mind is the brain.[3] Leibniz himself sought to bridge the gap by introducing monads to explain the existence of immaterial, eternal souls. Leibniz's gap, however, applies to materialism and dualism alike. This brought late 19th century scientists to conclude that psychology must build on introspection; thus introspectionism was born. Computationalism seeks to answer the problem proposed by Leibniz's gap through functional analysis of the brain and its processes. There is the position that functionalism could address the gap since it allows something to be described in terms of what it does without explaining how it does it or identifying the physical form it takes.[4] Today, however, Leibniz's gap is still in wide use in scientific debate as the mind body problem that remains unsolved.

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Cummins, Robert (2010-01-28). The World in the Head. OUP Oxford. ISBN 9780191609466.
  2. ^ Clapin, Hugh; Staines, Phillip; Slezak, Peter (2004). Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation. Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. xii. ISBN 008044394X.
  3. ^ Keil, Frank; Wilson, Robert (2000). Explanation and Cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press. p. 128. ISBN 0262112493.
  4. ^ Thompson, Mel (2012-10-12). Philosophy of Mind: Teach Yourself. Hodder & Stoughton. ISBN 9781444157642.