Human nature
Human nature is a bundle of characteristics (including ways of thinking, feeling, and acting) which humans are said to have naturally.[1][2][3][4] The term is often regarded as capturing what it is to be human, or the essence of humanity. The term is controversial because it is disputed whether or not such an essence exists. Arguments about human nature have been a mainstay of philosophy for centuries and the concept continues to provoke lively philosophical debate.[5][6][7] The concept also continues to play a role in science, with neuroscientists, psychologists and social scientists sometimes claiming that their results have yielded insight into human nature.[8][9][10][11] Human nature is traditionally contrasted with characteristics that vary among humans, such as characteristics associated with specific cultures. Debates about human nature are related to, although not the same as, debates about the comparative importance of genes and environment in development ("nature versus nurture").
Contents
- 1 Overview
- 2 Classical Greek philosophy
- 3 In Chinese thought
- 4 Christian theology
- 5 Early modern philosophy
- 6 Contemporary philosophy
- 7 See also
- 8 References
- 9 External links
Overview[edit]
The concept of nature as a standard by which to make judgments is traditionally said to have begun in Greek philosophy, at least as regards the Western and Middle Eastern languages and perspectives which are heavily influenced by it.[12]
The teleological approach of Aristotle came to be dominant by late classical and medieval times. By this account, human nature really causes humans to become what they become, and so it exists somehow independently of individual humans. This in turn has been understood as also showing a special connection between human nature and divinity. This approach understands human nature in terms of final and formal causes. In other words, nature itself (or a nature-creating divinity) has intentions and goals, similar somehow to human intentions and goals, and one of those goals is humanity living naturally. Such understandings of human nature see this nature as an "idea", or "form" of a human.[13]
However, the existence of this invariable and metaphysical human nature is a subject of much historical debate, continuing into modern times. Against this idea of a fixed human nature, the relative malleability of man has been argued especially strongly in recent centuries—firstly by early modernists such as Thomas Hobbes and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. In Rousseau's Emile, or On Education, Rousseau wrote: "We do not know what our nature permits us to be".[14] Since the early 19th century, thinkers such as Hegel, Marx, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Sartre, structuralists, and postmodernists have also sometimes argued against a fixed or innate human nature.
Charles Darwin's theory of evolution has changed the nature of the discussion, supporting the proposition that mankind's ancestors were not like mankind today. Still more recent scientific perspectives—such as behaviorism, determinism, and the chemical model within modern psychiatry and psychology—claim to be neutral regarding human nature. As in much of modern science, such disciplines seek to explain with little or no recourse to metaphysical causation.[15] They can be offered to explain human nature's origins and underlying mechanisms, or to demonstrate capacities for change and diversity which would arguably violate the concept of a fixed human nature.
Classical Greek philosophy[edit]
Philosophy in classical Greece is the ultimate origin[citation needed] of the Western conception of the nature of a thing. According to Aristotle, the philosophical study of human nature itself originated with Socrates, who turned philosophy from study of the heavens to study of the human things.[16] Socrates is said to have studied the question of how a person should best live, but he left no written works. It is clear from the works of his students Plato and Xenophon, and also by what was said about him by Aristotle (Plato's student), that Socrates was a rationalist and believed that the best life and the life most suited to human nature involved reasoning. The Socratic school was the dominant surviving influence in philosophical discussion in the Middle Ages, amongst Islamic, Christian, and Jewish philosophers.
The human soul in the works of Plato and Aristotle has a divided nature, divided in a specifically human way. One part is specifically human and rational, and divided into a part which is rational on its own, and a spirited part which can understand reason. Other parts of the soul are home to desires or passions similar to those found in animals. In both Aristotle and Plato, spiritedness (thumos) is distinguished from the other passions (epithumiai).[17] The proper function of the "rational" was to rule the other parts of the soul, helped by spiritedness. By this account, using one's reason is the best way to live, and philosophers are the highest types of humans.
Aristotle—Plato's most famous student—made some of the most famous and influential statements about human nature. In his works, apart from using a similar scheme of a divided human soul, some clear statements about human nature are made:
- Man is a conjugal animal, meaning an animal which is born to couple when an adult, thus building a household (oikos) and, in more successful cases, a clan or small village still run upon patriarchal lines.[18]
- Man is a political animal, meaning an animal with an innate propensity to develop more complex communities the size of a city or town, with a division of labor and law-making. This type of community is different in kind from a large family, and requires the special use of human reason.[19]
- Man is a mimetic animal. Man loves to use his imagination (and not only to make laws and run town councils). He says "we enjoy looking at accurate likenesses of things which are themselves painful to see, obscene beasts, for instance, and corpses." And the "reason why we enjoy seeing likenesses is that, as we look, we learn and infer what each is, for instance, 'that is so and so.'"[20]
For Aristotle, reason is not only what is most special about humanity compared to other animals, but it is also what we were meant to achieve at our best. Much of Aristotle's description of human nature is still influential today. However, the particular teleological idea that humans are "meant" or intended to be something has become much less popular in modern times.[21]
For the Socratics, human nature, and all natures, are metaphysical concepts. Aristotle developed the standard presentation of this approach with his theory of four causes. Every living thing exhibits four aspects or "causes": matter, form, effect, and end. For example, an oak tree is made of plant cells (matter), grew from an acorn (effect), exhibits the nature of oak trees (form), and grows into a fully mature oak tree (end). Human nature is an example of a formal cause, according to Aristotle. Likewise, to become a fully actualized human being (including fully actualizing the mind) is our end. Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics, Book X) suggests that the human intellect (νούς) is "smallest in bulk" but the most significant part of the human psyche, and should be cultivated above all else. The cultivation of learning and intellectual growth of the philosopher, which is thereby also the happiest and least painful life.
In Chinese thought[edit]
Human nature is a central question in Chinese philosophy.[22] Human nature was considered by Confucius and Mencius to be essentially good.[22] From the Song dynasty the theory of the original goodness of human beings dominated Confucian thought.[23] However, Hsun Tzu taught that human nature was essentially evil.[22] As suggested by these contrasting views, the question of human nature has generated a long debate among Chinese thinkers.[23]
Christian theology[edit]
In Christian theology, there are two ways of "conceiving human nature". The first is "spiritual, Biblical, and theistic", whereas the second is "natural, cosmical, and anti-theistic".[24] The focus in this section is on the former. As William James put it in his study of human nature from a religious perspective, "religion" has a "department of human nature".[25]
Various views of human nature have been held by theologians. However, there are some "basic assertions" in all "biblical anthropology".[26]
- "Humankind has its origin in God, its creator."
- "Humans bear the 'image of God'."
- Humans are "to rule the rest of creation".
The Bible contains no single "doctrine of human nature". Rather, it provides material for more philosophical descriptions of human nature.[27] For example, Creation as found in the Book of Genesis provides a theory on human nature.[28]
Catechism of the Catholic Church[29] in chapter "Dignity of the human person" has article about man as image of God, vocation to beatitude, freedom, human acts, passions, moral conscience, virtues and sin.
Created human nature[edit]
As originally created, the Bible describes "two elements" in human nature: "the body and the breath or spirit of life breathed into it by God". By this was created a "living soul", that is, a "living person".[30] According to Genesis 1:27, this living person was made in the "image of God".[31] From the biblical perspective, "to be human is to bear the image of God".[32]
Genesis does not elaborate the meaning of "the image of God", but scholars find suggestions. One is that being created in the image of God distinguishes human nature from that of the beasts.[33] Another is that as God is "able to make decisions and rule" so humans made in God's image are "able to make decisions and rule". A third is that mankind possesses an inherent ability "to set goals" and move toward them.[34] That God denoted creation as "good" suggests that Adam was "created in the image of God, in righteousness."[35]
Adam was created with ability to make "right choices", but also with the ability to choose sin, by which he fell from righteousness into a state of "sin and depravity".[36] Thus, according to the Bible, "humankind is not as God created it".[37]
Fallen human nature[edit]
By Adam's fall into sin, "human nature" became "corrupt", although it retains the image of God. Both the Old Testament and the New Testament teach that "sin is universal".[38] For example, Psalm 51:5 reads: "For behold I was conceived in iniquities; and in sins did my mother conceive me."[39] Jesus taught that everyone is a "sinner naturally" because it is mankind's "nature and disposition to sin".[40] Paul, in Romans 7:18, speaks of his "sinful nature".[41]
Such a "recognition that there is something wrong with the moral nature of man is found in all religions".[42] Augustine of Hippo coined a term for the assessment that all humans are born sinful: original sin.[43] Original sin is "the tendency to sin innate in all human beings".[44] The doctrine of original sin is held by the Catholic Church and most mainstream Protestant denominations, but rejected by the Eastern Orthodox Church, which holds the similar doctrine of ancestral fault.
"The corruption of original sin extends to every aspect of human nature": to "reason and will" as well as to "appetites and impulses". This condition is sometimes called "total depravity".[45] Total depravity does not mean that humanity is as "thoroughly depraved" as it could become.[46] Commenting on Romans 2:14, John Calvin writes that all people have "some notions of justice and rectitude ... which are implanted by nature" all people.[47]
Adam embodied the "whole of human nature" so when Adam sinned "all of human nature sinned".[48] The Old Testament does not explicitly link the "corruption of human nature" to Adam's sin. However, the "universality of sin" implies a link to Adam. In the New Testament, Paul concurs with the "universality of sin". He also makes explicit what the Old Testament implied: the link between humanity's "sinful nature" and Adam's sin[49] In Romans 5:19, Paul writes, "through [Adam's] disobedience humanity became sinful".[50] Paul also applied humanity's sinful nature to himself: "there is nothing good in my sinful nature."[51][52]
The theological "doctrine of original sin" as an inherent element of human nature is not based only on the Bible. It is in part a "generalization from obvious facts" open to empirical observation.[53]
Empirical view[edit]
A number of experts on human nature have described the manifestations of original (i.e., the innate tendency to) sin as empirical facts.
- Biologist Richard Dawkins in his The Selfish Gene states that "a predominant quality" in a successful surviving gene is "ruthless selfishness". Furthermore, "this gene selfishness will usually give rise to selfishness in individual behavior".[54]
- Child psychologist Burton L. White, PhD,[55] finds a "selfish" trait in children from birth, a trait that expresses itself in actions that are "blatantly selfish."[56]
- Sociologist William Graham Sumner finds it a fact that "everywhere one meets "fraud, corruption, ignorance, selfishness, and all the other vices of human nature".[57] He enumerates "the vices and passions of human nature" as "cupidity, lust, vindictiveness, ambition, and vanity". Sumner finds such human nature to be universal: in all people, in all places, and in all stations in society.[58]
- Psychiatrist Thomas Anthony Harris, MD, on the basis of his "data at hand", observes "sin, or badness, or evil, or 'human nature', whatever we call the flaw in our species, is apparent in every person". Harris calls this condition "intrinsic badness" or "original sin".[59]
Empirical discussion questioning the genetic exclusivity of such an intrinsic badness proposition is presented by researchers Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson. In their book, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, they propose a theory of multilevel group selection in support of an inherent genetic "altruism" in opposition to the original sin exclusivity for human nature.[60]
Realistic view[edit]
Liberal theologians in the early 20th century described human nature as "basically good", needing only "proper training and education". But the above examples document the return to a "more realistic view" of human nature "as basically sinful and self-centered". Human nature needs "to be regenerated ... to be able to live the unselfish life".[61]
Regenerated human nature[edit]
According to the Bible, "Adam's disobedience corrupted human nature" but God mercifully "regenerates".[62] "Regeneration is a radical change" that involves a "renewal of our [human] nature".[63] Thus, to counter original sin, Christianity purposes "a complete transformation of individuals" by Christ.[64]
The goal of Christ's coming is that fallen humanity might be "conformed to or transformed into the image of Christ who is the perfect image of God", as in 2 Corinthians 4:4.[65] The New Testament makes clear the "universal need" for regeneration.[66] A sampling of biblical portrayals of regenerating human nature and the behavioral results follow.
- being "transformed by the renewing of your minds" (Romans 12:2)[67]
- being transformed from one's "old self" (or "old man") into a "new self" (or "new man") (Col.3:9-10)[68]
- being transformed from people who "hate others" and "are hard to get along with" and who are "jealous, angry, and selfish" to people who are "loving, happy, peaceful, patient, kind, good, faithful, gentle, and self-controlled" (Galatians 5:20-23)[69]
- being transformed from looking "to your own interests" to looking "to the interests of others" (Philippians 2:4)[70]
Early modern philosophy[edit]
One of the defining changes that occurred at the end of the Middle Ages was the end of the dominance of Aristotelian philosophy, and its replacement by a new approach to the study of nature, including human nature.[citation needed] In this approach, all attempts at conjecture about formal and final causes were rejected as useless speculation.[citation needed] Also, the term "law of nature" now applied to any regular and predictable pattern in nature, not literally a law made by a divine lawmaker, and, in the same way, "human nature" became not a special metaphysical cause, but simply whatever can be said to be typical tendencies of humans.[citation needed]
Although this new realism applied to the study of human life from the beginning—for example, in Machiavelli's works—the definitive argument for the final rejection of Aristotle was associated especially with Francis Bacon. Bacon sometimes wrote as if he accepted the traditional four causes ("It is a correct position that "true knowledge is knowledge by causes". And causes again are not improperly distributed into four kinds: the material, the formal, the efficient, and the final") but he adapted these terms and rejected one of the three:
But of these the final cause rather corrupts than advances the sciences, except such as have to do with human action. The discovery of the formal is despaired of. The efficient and the material (as they are investigated and received, that is, as remote causes, without reference to the latent process leading to the form) are but slight and superficial, and contribute little, if anything, to true and active science.[71]
This line of thinking continued with René Descartes, whose new approach returned philosophy or science to its pre-Socratic focus upon non-human things. Thomas Hobbes, then Giambattista Vico, and David Hume all claimed to be the first to properly use a modern Baconian scientific approach to human things.
Hobbes famously followed Descartes in describing humanity as matter in motion, just like machines. He also very influentially described man's natural state (without science and artifice) as one where life would be "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short".[72] Following him, John Locke's philosophy of empiricism also saw human nature as a tabula rasa. In this view, the mind is at birth a "blank slate" without rules, so data are added, and rules for processing them are formed solely by our sensory experiences.[73]
Jean-Jacques Rousseau pushed the approach of Hobbes to an extreme and criticized it at the same time. He was a contemporary and acquaintance of Hume, writing before the French Revolution and long before Darwin and Freud. He shocked Western civilization with his Second Discourse by proposing that humans had once been solitary animals, without reason or language or communities, and had developed these things due to accidents of pre-history. (This proposal was also less famously made by Giambattista Vico.) In other words, Rousseau argued that human nature was not only not fixed, but not even approximately fixed compared to what had been assumed before him. Humans are political, and rational, and have language now, but originally they had none of these things.[74] This in turn implied that living under the management of human reason might not be a happy way to live at all, and perhaps there is no ideal way to live. Rousseau is also unusual in the extent to which he took the approach of Hobbes, asserting that primitive humans were not even naturally social. A civilized human is therefore not only imbalanced and unhappy because of the mismatch between civilized life and human nature, but unlike Hobbes, Rousseau also became well known for the suggestion that primitive humans had been happier, "noble savages".[75]
Rousseau's conception of human nature has been seen as the origin of many intellectual and political developments of the 19th and 20th centuries.[76] He was an important influence upon Kant, Hegel, and Marx, and the development of German idealism, historicism, and romanticism.
What human nature did entail, according to Rousseau and the other modernists of the 17th and 18th centuries, were animal-like passions that led humanity to develop language and reasoning, and more complex communities (or communities of any kind, according to Rousseau).
In contrast to Rousseau, David Hume was a critic of the oversimplifying and systematic approach of Hobbes, Rousseau, and some others whereby, for example, all human nature is assumed to be driven by variations of selfishness. Influenced by Hutcheson and Shaftesbury, he argued against oversimplification. On the one hand, he accepted that, for many political and economic subjects, people could be assumed to be driven by such simple selfishness, and he also wrote of some of the more social aspects of "human nature" as something which could be destroyed, for example if people did not associate in just societies. On the other hand, he rejected what he called the "paradox of the sceptics", saying that no politician could have invented words like "'honourable' and 'shameful,' 'lovely' and 'odious,' 'noble' and 'despicable'", unless there was not some natural "original constitution of the mind".[77]
Hume—like Rousseau—was controversial in his own time for his modernist approach, following the example of Bacon and Hobbes, of avoiding consideration of metaphysical explanations for any type of cause and effect. He was accused of being an atheist. He wrote:
We needn't push our researches so far as to ask "Why do we have humanity, i.e. a fellow-feeling with others?" It's enough that we experience this as a force in human nature. Our examination of causes must stop somewhere.[77]
After Rousseau and Hume, the nature of philosophy and science changed, branching into different disciplines and approaches, and the study of human nature changed accordingly. Rousseau's proposal that human nature is malleable became a major influence upon international revolutionary movements of various kinds, while Hume's approach has been more typical in Anglo-Saxon countries, including the United States.[citation needed]
Contemporary philosophy[edit]
The concept of human nature is a source of ongoing debate in contemporary philosophy, and especially in the philosophy of biology, a subfield of the philosophy of science. Critics of the concept – among the others, David L. Hull,[78] Michael Ghiselin,[79] and David Buller;[80] see also[5][6][7] – argue that it is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology. Defenders of the concept argue that, when defined in certain ways, it is both scientifically respectable and scientifically useful[81][82][83][5][6][7] and, therefore, that the value and usefulness of the concept of human nature depends essentially on its interpretation. This section offers a neutral overview of the debate, summarising the key arguments of both sides.
Criticism of the concept of human nature[edit]
Philosopher of science David L. Hull has influentially argued that there is no such thing as human nature, conceived as a set of intrinsic phenotypic traits (or characters) that are universal among humans, unique to humans, and definitive of what it is to be a member of the species Homo sapiens. Hull argues that variation is a normal feature of all biological species:
Periodically a biological species might be characterized by one or more characters which are both universally distributed among and limited to the organisms belonging to that species, but such states of affairs are temporary, contingent and relatively rare.[84]:3
Hull observes that, in contemporary evolutionary taxonomy, belonging to a particular species does not depend on the possession of any specific intrinsic properties. Instead, belonging to a species depends on standing in the right kind of relations (relations of genealogy or interbreeding, depending on the precise species concept being used) to other members of the species. It follows that there can be no intrinsic properties that define what it is to be a member of the species Homo sapiens.
Defences of the concept of human nature[edit]
Several contemporary philosophers have attempted to defend the notion of human nature against charges that it is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology. They claim that the concept of human nature continues to bear relevance in the fields of neuroscience and biology.
Machery's "nomological" account[edit]
Philosopher of science Edouard Machery has proposed that the above criticisms only apply to a specific definition (or 'notion') of human nature. He distinguishes between two types of notions:
- An essentialist notion of human nature on which human nature is the set of properties that are separately necessary and jointly sufficient for being a human.[85]
- A nomological notion of human nature on which human nature is the set of properties that humans tend to possess as a result of the evolution of their species.
Machery adds that, to count as being "a result of evolution", a property must have an ultimate explanation in Ernst Mayr's sense. It must be possible to explain the trait as the product of evolutionary processes. Importantly, properties can count as part of human nature in the nomological sense even if they are not universal among humans and not unique to humans. Human nature in the nomological sense does not define what it is to be a member of the species Homo sapiens.
Examples of properties that count as parts of human nature on the nomological definition include: being bipedal, having the capacity to speak, having a tendency towards biparental investment in children, having fear reactions to unexpected noises.[85] Machery agrees with evolutionary biologists that the essentialist notion of human nature is mistaken: we cannot explain membership in the human species by means of a definition or a set of properties. However, he maintains that this does not mean humans have no nature, because we can accept the nomological notion which is not a definitional notion. Therefore, we should think of human nature as the many properties humans have in common as a result of evolution.[85]
Problems for the nomological account[edit]
Machery also highlights potential drawbacks of the nomological account.[85] One is that the nomological notion is a watered-down notion that can't perform many of the roles that the concept of human nature is expected to perform in science and philosophy. The properties endowed upon humans by the nomological account do not distinguish humans from other animals or define what it is to be human. Machery pre-empts this objection by claiming that the nomological concept of human nature still fulfils many roles. Claiming that a particular property belongs to human nature is to say that this trait is displayed by the majority of human beings and that its existence can be explained in evolutionary terms.
Another potential drawback is that the nomological account of human nature threatens to lead to the absurd conclusion that all properties of humans are parts of human nature. According to the nomological account, a trait is only part of human nature if it is a result of evolution. However, there is a sense in which all human traits are results of evolution. For example, the belief that water is wet is shared by all humans. However, this belief is only possible because we have, for example, evolved a sense of touch. It is difficult to separate traits which are the result of evolution and those which are not. Machery claims the distinction between proximate and ultimate explanation can do the work here: only some human traits can be given an ultimate explanation, he argues.
According to the philosopher Richard Samuels[83] the account of human nature is expected to fulfill the five following roles:
- an organizing function that demarks a territory of scientific inquiry
- a descriptive function that is traditionally understood as specifying properties that are universal across and unique to human being
- a causal explanatory function that offers causal explanation for occurring human behaviours and features
- a taxonomic function that specifies possessing human nature as a necessary and sufficient criterion for belonging to the human species
- Invariances that assume the understanding that human nature is to some degree fixed, invariable or at least hard to change
Samuels objects that Machery's nomological account fails to deliver on the causal explanatory function, because it claims that superficial and co-varying properties are the essence of human nature. Thus, human nature cannot be the underlying cause of these properties and accordingly cannot fulfill its causal explanatory role.
Philosopher Grant Ramsey also rejects Machery's nomological account. For him, defining human nature with respect to only universal traits fails to capture many important human characteristics.[81] Ramsey quotes the anthropologist Clifford Geertz, who claims that "the notion that unless a cultural phenomenon is empirically universal it cannot reflect anything about the nature of man is about as logical as the notion that because sickle-cell anemia is, fortunately, not universal, it cannot tell us anything about human genetic processes. It is not whether phenomena are empirically common that is critical in science...but whether they can be made to reveal the enduring natural processes that underly them".[86] Following Geertz, Ramsey holds that the study of human nature should not rely exclusively on universal or near-universal traits. There are many idiosyncratic and particular traits of scientific interest. For example, female menopause is a biologically interesting feature of human nature, despite being present in only about half the population.[81]
Ramsey[81] also objects that Machery uncritically adopts the innate-acquired dichotomy, distinguishing between human properties due to enculturation and those due to evolution. Ramsey objects that human properties do not just fall in one of the two categories, writing that "any organismic property is going to be due to both heritable features of the organism as well as the particular environmental features the organism happens to encounter during its life."[81]
Samuels' "causal essentialist" account[edit]
Richard Samuels (in his article Science and Human Nature) proposes a causal essentialist view that "human nature should be identified with a suite of mechanisms, processes, and structures that causally explain many of the more superficial properties and regularities reliably associated with humanity".[83] This view is "causal" because the mechanisms causally explain many of the more superficial properties and regularities reliably associated with humanity. On the other hand, is "essentialist" because there is a core set of empirically discoverable cognitive mechanism that count as part of the human nature. According to Samuels, his view avoids the standard biological objections to human nature essentialism.
Samuels argues that the theoretical roles of human nature includes: organizing role, descriptive functions, causal explanatory functions, taxonomic functions, and invariances.
In comparison with traditional essentialist view, the "causal essentialist" view does not accomplish the taxonomic role of human nature (the role of defining what it is to be human). He claims however, that no conception could achieve this, as the fulfillment of the role would not survive evolutionary biologists’ objections. In comparison with Machery’s nomological conception, Samuels wants to restore the causal-explanatory function of human nature. He defines the essence of human nature as causal mechanisms and not as surface-level properties. For instance, on this view, linguistic behaviour is not part of human nature, but the cognitive mechanisms underpinning linguistic behaviour might count as part of human nature.
Ramsey's "life-history trait cluster" account[edit]
Grant Ramsey proposes an alternative account of human nature, which he names the "life-history trait cluster" account.[81] This view stems from the recognition that the combination of a specific genetic constitution with a specific environment is not sufficient by itself to determine how a life will go, i.e., whether one is rich, poor, dies old, dies young, etc. Many ‘life histories’ are possible for a given individual, each populated by a great number of traits (a ‘trait’ on Ramsey’s account just denotes any property of a life).[81]
Ramsey next argumentative manoeuvre is to point out that traits are not randomly scattered across potential life histories; there are patterns. “These patterns” he states “provide the basis for the notion of individual and human nature”.[81]:987 While one’s ‘individual nature’ consists of the pattern of trait clusters distributed across that individual’s set of possible life histories, Human Nature, Ramsey defines as “the pattern of trait clusters within the totality of extant human possible life histories”.[81]:987 Thus, were we to combine all possible life histories of all individuals in existence we would have access to the trait distribution patterns that constitute human nature.
Trait patterns can be captured in the form of conditional statements, such as "if female, you develop ovaries" or "if male, you develop testes". These statements will not be true of all humans. But, for Ramsey, these statements capture part of human nature if they have a good balance of pervasiveness (many people satisfy the antecedent of the conditional statement) and robustness (many people who satisfy the antecedent go on to satisfy the consequent).
Transhumanism and bioconservatism[edit]
The contemporary debate between so-called “bioconservatives” and “transhumanists” is directly related to the concept of human nature and to its different interpretations. In particular, bioconservatives present their position as a defense of human nature which, according to them, is threatened by human enhancement technologies. Prominent bioconservatives are Jürgen Habermas,[87] Leon Kass,[88] Francis Fukuyama,[89] George Annas, Wesley Smith, Jeremy Rifkin, and Bill McKibben.[90] Some of the reasons why they oppose (certain forms of) human enhancement technology are to be found in the worry that they would be “dehumanizing” (as they would undermine the human dignity intrinsically built in our human nature). For instance, they fear that becoming “posthumans” could pose a threat to “ordinary” humans [91] or be harmful to posthumans themselves.[92][90] Additionally, and in the specific case of genetic modification of unborn childs by their parents, it has been argued that human enhancement would be constitutionally forbidden, since it would violate the ethical freedom of the unborn, subjecting them to decisions they would not be able to control or reverse, and affect the symmetrical relations of equality that are characteristic of a constitutional democracy[93].
The most famous proponent of transhumanism, on the other hand, is Oxford Swedish philosopher Nick Bostrom. According to Bostrom, human enhancement technologies should be made widely available, as they would offer enormous potential for improving the lives of human beings, without "dehumanizing" them: for instance, extending their intellectual and physical capacities, or protecting them from suffering, illnesses, aging, and cognitive shortcomings.[90] In response to bioconservatives, transhumanists argue that expanding a person's 'capability set' would increase her freedom of choice, rather than reducing it[90].
Although the debate between bioconvervatives and transhumanists is mainly of an ethical kind, it is deeply rooted in the different interpretations of human nature, and in the idea of human dignity that stems from this concept (which, according to bioconservatives, is specific to human beings, while transhumanists think that it can be possessed also by posthumans).
See also[edit]
References[edit]
- ^ "Definition of HUMAN NATURE". www.merriam-webster.com.
- ^ "human nature".
- ^ "the definition of human nature". Dictionary.com.
- ^ "human nature Meaning in the Cambridge English Dictionary". dictionary.cambridge.org.
- ^ a b c Hannon, Elizabeth; Lewens, Tim, eds. (2018-07-19). "Why We Disagree About Human Nature". Oxford Scholarship Online. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198823650.001.0001.
- ^ a b c Kronfeldner, Maria; Roughley, Neil; Toepfer, Georg (2014-09). "Recent Work on Human Nature: Beyond Traditional Essences". Philosophy Compass. 9 (9): 642–652. doi:10.1111/phc3.12159. ISSN 1747-9991. Check date values in:
|date=
(help) - ^ a b c Downes, Stephen M.; Machery, Edouard, eds. (2013). Arguing About Human Nature: Contemporary Debates. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0415894401.
- ^ Ramachandran, V. S. (1996). "What neurological syndromes can tell us about human nature: some lessons from phantom limbs, capgras syndrome, and anosognosia". Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology. 61: 115–134. ISSN 0091-7451. PMID 9246441.
- ^ Blank, Robert H. (2002). "Review of Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur. 2000. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain". The American journal of bioethics: AJOB. 2 (4): 69–70. doi:10.1162/152651602320957718. ISSN 1536-0075. PMID 22494253.
- ^ Fowler, James H.; Schreiber, Darren (2008-11-07). "Biology, politics, and the emerging science of human nature". Science. 322 (5903): 912–914. doi:10.1126/science.1158188. ISSN 1095-9203. PMID 18988845.
- ^ Paulson, Steve; Berlin, Heather A.; Miller, Christian B.; Shermer, Michael (2016). "The moral animal: virtue, vice, and human nature". Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 1384 (1): 39–56. doi:10.1111/nyas.13067. ISSN 1749-6632. PMID 27248691.
- ^ "Progress or Refurn" in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.
- ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1078b.
- ^ Saunders, Jason Lewis (1995). "Western Philosophical Schools and Doctrines: Ancient and Medieval Schools: Sophists: Particular Doctrines: Theoretical issues". Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 27 May 2011. Retrieved 7 February 2011.
- ^ "TELEOLOGICAL REALISM IN BIOLOGY". www.academia.edu. Retrieved 2016-02-23.
- ^ Aristotle's Metaphysics
- ^ Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics Book I and VI; Plato Republic Book IV.
- ^ Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VIII. 1162a; Politics 1252a.
- ^ Aristotle, Politics 1252b.
- ^ Aristotle, Poetics 1148b.
- ^ Aristotle, The Politics of Aristotle: With an Introduction, Two Prefactory Essays and Notes Critical and Explanatory, Clarendon Press, 1887, Pg. 189–190
- ^ a b c Paul C Tang and N Basafa, Human Nature in Chinese Thought: A Wittgensteinian Treatment. Proceedings of the 12th International Wittgenstein Symposium 1988
- ^ a b Yen, Hung-Chung. "Human Nature and Learning in Ancient China." Education as Cultivation in Chinese Culture. Springer Singapore, 2015. 19-43.
- ^ a b John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 6.
- ^ William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (The Modern Library, 1902), 473.
- ^ Justo L. González, Essential Theological Terms s.v. "Anthropoology" (Westminster John Knox, 2005), 8.
- ^ Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), s.v. "Human Being, Doctrine of," 310.
- ^ Ackerman, Kenneth. "Anthropology and Human Nature, 13" (PDF).
- ^ "Catechism of the Catholic Church - IntraText". www.vatican.va.
- ^ Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Eerdmans, 1996), 183.
- ^ "Genesis Chapter 1 (NIV)".
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 18.
- ^ Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), s. v. "Image of God," 318-319.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 5, 14.
- ^ James Wood, A Dictionary of the Holy Bible (Griffin and Rudd, 1813), 34.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 231.
- ^ Malcolm Jeeves, Human Nature: Reflections on the Integration of Psychology and Christianity (Templeton ,2006), 115.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 17, 141.
- ^ Psalm 51:5
- ^ John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 124-125.
- ^ "Romans 7:18. - - Bible Gateway". www.biblegateway.com.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 141.
- ^ Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), 312.
- ^ "original sin" in The Oxford Pocket Dictionary of Current English (Oxford University, 2009).
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 152.
- ^ Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Eerdmans, 1996), 246.
- ^ Calvin, John. "2". Commentary on Romans.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 158.
- ^ James Hastings, ed., A Dictionary of the Bible: Pleroma-Zuzim (C. Scribner's Sons, 1902) s. v. "Sin," 528, 534.
- ^ "Bible Gateway passage: Romans 5:19 - GOD'S WORD Translation". Bible Gateway.
- ^ "Romans 7:18 - NIRV - I know there is nothing good in my sinful natur..." Bible Study Tools.
- ^ "Sarx - New Testament Greek Lexicon - New American Standard". Bible Study Tools.
- ^ John Tulloch, Christian Doctrine of Sin (Scribner, Armstrong, 1876), 175.
- ^ Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford University, 1989), 2-3.
- ^ "Dr. Burton White, 84, believed children should avoid day care - The Boston Globe".
- ^ Burton L. White, Raising a Happy, Unspoiled Child (Touchstone; Rev ed, 1995), 98, 269.
- ^ William Graham Sumner (1914). The Challenge of Facts and Other Essays. Yale University. p. 233.
- ^ "What Social Classes Owe to Each Other". Harper & Brothers. 1883.
- ^ Thomas A. Harris, I'm OK — You're OK (HarperCollins, 2004, Quill edition), 233.
- ^ Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 394 pp., ISBN 0-674-93046-0
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 187-188.
- ^ Walter A. Elwell, ed, Evangelical Dictionary of Theology (Baker, 2001), 399.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 101.
- ^ Kevin J. Vanhoozer, gen. ed., Dictionary for Theological Interpretation of the Bible (Baker, 2005), 135, 313.
- ^ Anthony A. Hoekema, Created in God's Image (Eerdmans, 1986), 21, 24.
- ^ Watson E. Mills, Roger Aubrey Bullard, eds, Mercer Dictionary of the Bible (Mercer University, 1990), 741.
- ^ "Bible Gateway passage: Romans 12:2 - New Revised Standard Version". Bible Gateway.
- ^ "Colossians Chapter 3 (NIV)".
- ^ "Bible Gateway passage: Galatians 5:20-23 - Contemporary English Version". Bible Gateway.
- ^ "Bible Gateway passage: Philippians 2:4 - New Revised Standard Version". Bible Gateway.
- ^ "Francis Bacon: Novum Organum (1620)". www.constitution.org. pp. Book II, Section II. Retrieved 2016-02-23.
- ^ Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, XIII.9
- ^ Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.), Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN, 1996, pp. 33–36.
- ^ Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Social Contract, Translated by Maurice Cranston, Published by Penguin Classics, 1968, ISBN 0-14-044201-4, pg. 136
- ^ Velkley, Richard (2002), Being after Rousseau: Philosophy and Culture in Question, University of Chicago Press
- ^ Delaney, James, Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2006, ISBN 0-8264-8724-6, pg. 49–52
- ^ a b An Enquiry into the Sources of Morals Section 5.1
- ^ Hull, David L. (January 1986). "On Human Nature". PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. 1986 (2): 3–13. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1986.2.192787. ISSN 0270-8647.
- ^ Ghiselin, Michael T. (1997). Metaphysics and the origins of species. Albany: State University of New York Press.
- ^ Buller, David J. (2005). Adapting minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Ramsey, Grant (December 2013). "Human Nature in a Post-essentialist World". Philosophy of Science. 80 (5): 983–993. doi:10.1086/673902. ISSN 0031-8248. Retrieved 2019-01-21 – via ResearchGate.
- ^ Machery, Edouard (June 2008). "A Plea for Human Nature". Philosophical Psychology. 21 (3): 321–329. doi:10.1080/09515080802170119. ISSN 0951-5089.
- ^ a b c Samuels, Richard (2012). "Science and Human Nature". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. 70: 1–28 – via PhilPapers.
- ^ Hull, David L. (January 1986). "On Human Nature". PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. 1986 (2): 3–13. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1986.2.192787. ISSN 0270-8647.
- ^ a b c d Machery, Edouard (June 2008). "A Plea for Human Nature". Philosophical Psychology. 21 (3): 321–329. doi:10.1080/09515080802170119. ISSN 0951-5089.
- ^ Geertz, Clifford (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books. p. 44.
- ^ Habermas, Jurgen (2003). The Future of Human Nature.
- ^ Kass, Leon (2003). "Happy Souls: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Perfection". The New Atlantis. 1.
- ^ Fukuyama, Francis (2002). Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
- ^ a b c d Bostrom, Nick (2005). "In Defense of Posthuman Dignity". Bioethics. 19 (3): 202–14.
- ^ G. Annas, L. Andrews, and R. Isasi (2002). "Protecting the Endangered Human: Toward an International Treaty Prohibiting Cloning and Inheritable Alterations". American Journal of Law and Medicine. 28 (2–3): 162.CS1 maint: Uses authors parameter (link)
- ^ Kass, Leon (2002). Life, Liberty, and Defense of Dignity: The Challenge for Bioethics. San Francisco: Encounter Books.
- ^ Habermas, Jurgen (2003). The Future of Human Nature. pp. 60–66.
Library resources about Human nature |
External links[edit]
Wikiquote has quotations related to: Human nature |
- "Human Nature", BBC Radio 4 discussion with Steven Pinker, Janet Radcliffe Richards & John Gray (In Our Time, Nov. 7, 2002)