Stoic logic

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Stoic logic is the system of propositional logic developed by the Stoic philosophers in ancient Greece. It was one of the two great systems of logic in the classical world. It was largely built and shaped by Chrysippus, the third head of the Stoic school in the 3rd-century BCE. Chrysippus's logic differed from Aristotle's term logic because it was based on the analysis of propositions rather than terms. The smallest unit in Stoic logic is an assertible (the Stoic equivalent of a proposition) which is the content of a statement such as "it is day". Assertibles have a truth-value such that at any moment of time they are either true or false. Compound assertibles can be built up from simple ones through the use of logical connectives. The resulting syllogistic was grounded on five basic indemonstrable arguments to which all other syllogisms were claimed to be reducible.

Towards the end of antiquity Stoic logic was neglected in favour of Aristotle's logic, and as a result the Stoic writings on logic did not survive, and the only accounts of it were incomplete reports by other writers. Knowledge about Stoic logic as a system was lost until the 20th-century when logicians familiar with the modern propositional calculus reappraised the ancient accounts of it.

Background[edit]

Stoicism is a school of philosophy which developed in the Hellenistic period around a generation after the time of Aristotle.[1] The Stoics believed that the universe operated according to reason, i.e. by a God which is immersed in nature itself.[1] Logic (logike) was the part of philosophy which examined reason (logos).[2] To achieve a happy life—a life worth living—requires logical thought.[1] The Stoics held that an understanding of ethics was impossible without logic.[3] In the words of Brad Inwood, the Stoics believed that:[4]

Logic helps a person see what is the case, reason effectively about practical affairs, stand his or her ground amid confusion, differentiate the certain from the probable, and so forth.

Chrysippus, who created much of Stoic logic

Aristotle's term logic can be viewed as a logic of classification.[5] It makes use of four logical terms "all", "some", "is/are", and "is/are not" and to that extent is fairly static.[5][6] The Stoics needed a logic that examines choice and consequence.[3] The Stoics therefore developed a logic of propositions which uses connectives such as "if ... then", "either ... or", and "not both".[7] Such connectives are part of everyday reasoning.[7] Socrates in the Dialogues of Plato often asks a fellow citizen if they believe a certain thing; when they agree, Socrates then proceeds to show how the consequences are logically false or absurd, inferring that the original belief must be wrong.[7] Similar attempts at forensic reasoning must have been used in the law-courts, and they are a fundamental part of Greek mathematics.[7] Aristotle himself was familiar with propositions, and his pupils Theophrastus and Eudemus had examined hypothetical syllogisms, but there was no attempt by the Peripatetic school to develop these ideas into a system of logic.[8]

The Stoic tradition of logic originated in the 4th-century BCE in a different school of philosophy known as the Megarian school.[9] It was two dialeticians of this school, Diodorus Cronus and his pupil Philo, who developed their own theories of modalities and of conditional propositions.[9] The founder of Stoicism, Zeno of Citium, studied under the Megarians and he was said to have been a fellow pupil with Philo.[10] However, the outstanding figure in the development of Stoic logic was Chrysippus of Soli (c. 279 – c. 206 BCE), the third head of the Stoic school.[9] Chrysippus shaped much of Stoic logic as we know it creating a system of propositional logic.[11] As a logician Chrysippus is sometimes said to rival Aristotle in stature.[10] The logical writings by Chrysippus are, however, almost entirely lost,[9] instead his system has to be reconstructed from the partial and incomplete accounts preserved in the works of later authors such as Sextus Empiricus, Diogenes Laërtius, and Galen.[10]

Propositions[edit]

To the Stoics, logic was a wide field of knowledge which included the study of language, grammar, rhetoric and epistemology.[2] However, all of these fields were interrelated, and the Stoics developed their logic (or "dialectic") within the context of their theory of language and epistemology.[12]

Assertibles[edit]

The Stoics held that any meaningful utterance will involve three items: the sounds uttered; the thing which is referred to or described by the utterance; and an incorporeal item—the "sayable" (lekton)—that which is conveyed in the language.[13] The lekton is not a statement but the content of a statement, and it corresponds to a complete utterance.[14][15] A lekton can be something such as a question or a command, but Stoic logic operates on those lekta which are called "assertibles" (axiomata), described as a proposition which is either true or false and which affirms or denies.[14][16] Examples of assertibles include "it is night", "it is raining this afternoon", and "no one is walking."[17][18] The assertibles are truth-bearers.[19] They can never be true and false at the same time (law of noncontradiction) and they must be at least true or false (law of excluded middle).[20] The Stoics catalogued these simple assertibles according to whether they are affirmative or negative, and whether they are definite or indefinite (or both).[21] The assertibles are much like modern propositions, however their truth value can change depending on when they are asserted.[22] Thus an assertible such as "it is night" will only be true when it is night and not when it is day.[16]

Compound assertibles[edit]

Simple assertibles can be connected to each other to form compound or non-simple assertibles.[23] This is achieved through the use of logical connectives.[23] Chrysippus seems to have been responsible for introducing the three main types of connectives: the conditional (if), conjunctive (and), and disjunctive (or).[24] A typical conditional takes the form of "if p then q";[25] whereas a conjunction takes the form of "both p and q";[25] and a disjunction takes the form of "either p or q".[26] The or they used is exclusive, unlike the inclusive or generally used in modern formal logic.[27] These connectives are combined with the use of not for negation.[28] Thus the conditional can take the following four forms:[29]

If p, then q | If not p, then q | If p, then not q | If not p, then not q

Later Stoics added more connectives: the pseudo-conditional took the form of "since p then q"; and the causal assertible took the form of "because p then q".[a] There was also a comparative (or dissertive): "more/less (likely) p than q".[30]

Logical connectives
Name Type Example
Conditional if if it is day, it is light
Conjunction and it is day and light
Disjunction either ... or either it is day or night
Pseudo-conditional since since it is day, it is light
Causal because because it is day, it is light
Comparative more/less likely ... than more likely it is day than night

Modality[edit]

Assertibles can also be distinguished by their modal properties[b]—whether they are possible, impossible, necessary, or non-necessary.[31] In this the Stoics were building on an earlier Megarian debate initiated by Diodorus Cronus.[31] Diodorus had defined possibility in a way which seemed to adopt a form of fatalism.[32] Diodorus defined possible as "that which either is or will be true".[33] Thus there are no possibilities that are forever unrealised, whatever is possible is or one day will be true.[32] His pupil Philo, rejecting this, defined possible as "that which is capable of being true by the proposition's own nature",[33] thus a statement like "this piece of wood can burn" is possible, even if it spent its entire existence on the bottom of the ocean.[34] Chrysippus, on the other hand, was a causal determinist: he thought that true causes inevitably give rise to their effects and that all things arise in this way.[35] But he was not a logical determinist or fatalist: he wanted to distinguish between possible and necessary truths.[35] Thus he took a middle position between Diodorus and Philo, combining elements of both their modal systems.[36] Chrysippus's set of Stoic modal definitions was as follows:[37]

Modal definitions
Name Definition
possible An assertible which can become true and is not hindered by external things from becoming true
impossible An assertible which cannot become true or which can become true but is hindered by external things from becoming true
necessary An assertible which (when true) cannot become false or which can become false but is hindered by external things from becoming false
non-necessary An assertible which can become false and is not hindered by external things from becoming false

Syllogistic[edit]

Arguments[edit]

In Stoic logic, an argument form contains two (or more) premisses related to one another as cause and effect.[38] A typical Stoic syllogism is:[39]

If it is day, it is light;
It is day;
Therefore it is light.

It has a non-simple assertible for the first premiss ("If it is day, it is light") and a simple assertible for second premiss ("It is day").[39] The second premiss doesn't always have to be simple but it will have fewer components than the first.[39]

In more formal terms this type of syllogism is:[16]

If p, then q;
p;
Therefore q.

Thus, like Aristotle's term logic, Stoic logic uses variables, but the values of the variables are propositions not terms.[40] Chrysippus listed five basic argument forms, which he regarded as true beyond dispute.[c] These five indemonstrable arguments are made up of conditional, disjunction, and negation conjunction connectives,[41] and all other arguments are reducible to these five indemonstrable arguments.[15]

Indemonstrable arguments
Name[d] Description Example
Modus ponens If p, then q.  p.  Therefore, q. If it is day, it is light. It is day. Therefore, it is light.
Modus tollens If p, then q.  Not q.  Therefore, not p. If it is day, it is light. It is not light. Therefore, it is not day.
  Not both p and q.  p.  Therefore, not q.  It is not both day and night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night. 
Modus tollendo ponens Either p or q.  Not p.  Therefore, q. It is either day or night. It is not day. Therefore, it is night.
Modus ponendo tollens Either p or q.  p.  Therefore, not q. It is either day or night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night.

There can be many variations of these five indemonstrable arguments.[42] For example the assertibles in the premisses can be more complex, and the following syllogism is a valid example of the second indemonstrable (modus tollens):[29]

if both p and q, then r;
not r;
therefore not: both p and q

Similarly one can incorporate negation into these arguments.[29] A valid example of the fourth indemonstrable (modus tollendo ponens or disjunctive syllogism) is:[43]

either [not p] or q;
not [not p];
therefore q

which, incorporating the principle of double negation, is equivalent to:[43]

either [not p] or q;
p;
therefore q

Analysis[edit]

Many arguments are not in the form of the five indemonstrables, and the task is to show how they can be reduced to one of the five types.[28] A simple example of Stoic reduction is reported by Sextus Empiricus:[44]

if both p and q, then r;
not r;
but also p;
Therefore not q

This can be reduced to two separate indemonstrable arguments of the second and third type:[45]

if both p and q, then r;
not r;
therefore not: both p and q
not: both p and q
p;
therefore not q

The Stoics stated that complex syllogisms could be reduced to the indemonstrables through the use of four ground rules or themata.[40] Of these four themata, only two have survived.[33] One, the so-called first thema, was a rule of antilogism:[33]

When from two [assertibles] a third follows, then from either of them together with the contradictory of the conclusion the contradictory of the other follows (Apuleius, De Interpretatione 209. 9–14).

The other, the third thema, was a cut rule by which chain syllogisms could be reduced to simple syllogisms.[e] The importance of these rules is not altogether clear.[46] In the 2nd-century BCE Antipater of Tarsus is said to have introduced a simpler method involving the use of fewer themata, although few details survive concerning this.[46] In any case, the themata cannot have been a necessary part of every analysis.[47]

Paradoxes[edit]

Why should not the philosopher develop his own reason? You turn to vessels of crystal, I to the syllogism called The Liar; you to myrrhine glassware, I to the syllogism called The Denyer.

Epictetus, Discourses, iii.9.20

Next to describing inferences which are valid, another subject which engaged the Stoics was the enumeration and refutation of false arguments, and in particular of paradoxes.[48] Part of a Stoic's logical training was to prepare the philosopher for paradoxes and help find solutions.[49] A false argument could be one with a false premiss or which is formally incorrect, however paradoxes represented a challenge to the basic logical notions of the Stoics such as truth or falsehood.[50] One famous paradox, known as The Liar, asked "A man says he is lying; is what he says true or false?"—if the man says something true then it seems he is lying, but if he is lying then he is not saying something true, and so on.[51] Chrysippus is known to have written several books on this paradox, although it is not known what solution he offered for it.[52] Another paradox known as the Sorites or "Heap" asked "How many grains of wheat do you need before you get a heap?"[52] It was said to challenge the idea of true or false by offering up the possibility of vagueness.[52] The response of Chrysippus however was: "That doesn't harm me, for like a skilled driver I shall restrain my horses before I reach the edge ... In like manner I restrain myself in advance and stop replying to sophistical questions."[52]

Stoic practice[edit]

Training in logic included a mastery of logical puzzles, the study of paradoxes, and the dissection of arguments.[53] However, it was not an end in itself, but rather its purpose was for the Stoics to cultivate their rational powers.[54]

Logic, for instance, was not limited to an abstract theory of reasoning, nor even to school exercises in syllogistics; rather, there was a daily practice of logic applied to the problems of everyday life. Logic was thus the mastery of inner discourse. ... The Stoics believed that the human passions correspond to a misuse of human discourse. In other words, they are the result of errors in judgement and in reasoning. We must therefore monitor our inner discourse to see whether erroneous value judgments have crept into it.[55]

Stoic logic was thus a method of self-discovery.[56] Its aim was to enable ethical reflection, permit secure and confident arguing, and lead the pupil to truth.[53] The end result would be thought that is consistent, clear and precise, and which exposes confusion, murkiness and inconsistency.[57] Diogenes Laërtius gives a list of dialectical virtues, which were probably invented by Chrysippus:[58]

First he mentions aproptosia, which means literally 'not falling forward' and is defined as 'knowledge of when one should give assent or not' (give assent); next aneikaiotes, 'unhastiness', defined as 'strong-mindedness against the probable (or plausible), so as not to give in to it'; third, anelenxia, 'irrefutability', the definition of which is 'strength in argument, so as not to be driven by it to the contradictory'; and fourth, amataiotes, 'lack of emptyheadedness', defined as 'a disposition which refers impressions (phantasiai) to the correct logos.[58]

Later reception[edit]

For around five hundred years Stoic logic was one of the two great systems of logic.[59] The logic of Chrysippus was discussed alongside that of Aristotle, and it may well have been more prominent since Stoicism was the dominant philosophical school.[60] From a modern perspective Aristotle's term logic and the Stoic logic of propositions appear complementary, but they were sometimes regarded as rival systems.[28] In late antiquity the Stoic school fell into decline, and the last pagan philosophical school, the Neoplatonists, adopted Aristotle's logic for their own.[61] Only elements of Stoic logic made their way into the logical writings of later commentators such as Boethius, transmitting confused parts of Stoic logic to the Middle Ages.[60] Propositional logic was redeveloped by Peter Abelard in the 12th-century, but by the mid-15th-century the only logic which was being studied was a simplified version of Aristotle's.[62] In the 18th-century Immanuel Kant could pronounce that "since Aristotle ... logic has not been able to advance a single step, and is thus to all appearance a closed and complete body of doctrine."[63] To 19th-century historians, who believed that Hellenistic philosophy represented a decline from that of Plato and Aristotle, Stoic logic could only be seen with contempt.[64] Carl Prantl thought that Stoic logic was "dullness, triviality, and scholastic quibbling" and he welcomed the fact that the works of Chrysippus were no longer extant.[65] Eduard Zeller remarked that "the whole contribution of the Stoics to the field of logic consists in their having clothed the logic of the Peripatetics with a new terminology."[66]

Modern logic begins in the middle of the 19th-century with the work of George Boole and Augustus de Morgan,[62] but Stoic logic was only rediscovered in the 20th-century.[65] The first person to reappraise their ideas was the Polish logician Jan Łukasiewicz from the 1920s onwards.[65] He was followed by Benson Mates.[65] Although strikingly modern, Stoic logic was not a formal system in the modern sense, since their motivation was to study their ethical psychology and their general theory of nature (Stoic physics).[12] Stoic concepts often differ from modern ones, but nevertheless there are many close parallels between Stoic and 20th-century theories.[67]

What we see as a result is a close similarity between [these] methods of reasoning and the behaviour of digital computers. ... The code happens to come from the nineteeth-century logician and mathematician George Boole, whose aim was to codify the relations studied much earlier by Chrysippus (albeit with greater abstraction and sophistication). Later generations built on Boole's insights ... but the logic that made it all possible was the interconnected logic of an interconnected universe, discovered by the ancient Chrysippus, who labored long ago under an old Athenian stoa.[68]

Notes[edit]

a. ^ The minimum requirement for a conditional is that the consequent follows from the antecedent.[25] The pseudo-conditional adds that the antecedent must be also be true. The causal assertible adds an asymmetry rule such that if p is the cause/reason for q, then q cannot be the cause/reason for p. Bobzien 1999, p. 109
b. ^ "Stoic modal logic is not a logic of modal propositions (e.g., propositions of the type 'It is possible that it is day' ...) ... instead, their modal theory was about non-modalized propositions like 'It is day', insofar as they are possible, necessary, and so forth." Bobzien 1999, p. 117
c. ^ Most of these argument forms had already been discussed by Theophrastus, but: "It is plain that even if Theophrastus discussed (1)–(5), he did not anticipate Chrysippus' achievement. ... his Aristotelian approach to the study and organization of argument-forms would have given his discussion of mixed hypothetical syllogisms an utterly unStoical aspect." Barnes 1999, p. 83
d. ^ These Latin names date from the Middle Ages. Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 288
e. ^ For a brief summary of these themata see Susanne Bobzien's Ancient Logic article for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. For a detailed (and technical) analysis of the themata, including a tentative reconstruction of the two lost ones, see Bobzien 1999, pp. 137–148

Citations[edit]

  1. ^ a b c Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 74
  2. ^ a b Sellars 2006, p. 55
  3. ^ a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 78
  4. ^ Inwood 2003, p. 229
  5. ^ a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 73
  6. ^ Sellars 2006, p. 57
  7. ^ a b c d Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 79
  8. ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 507
  9. ^ a b c d Bobzien 1996, p. 880
  10. ^ a b c Sellars 2006, p. 56
  11. ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 80
  12. ^ a b O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 400
  13. ^ Everson 1994, p. 85
  14. ^ a b Johansen & Rosenmeier 1998, p. 466
  15. ^ a b Ierodiakonou 2006, p. 678
  16. ^ a b c Sellars 2006, p. 58
  17. ^ Sellars 2006, pp. 58–9
  18. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 102
  19. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 92
  20. ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 88
  21. ^ Bobzien 1999, pp. 97–8
  22. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 95
  23. ^ a b Bobzien 1999, p. 103
  24. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 105
  25. ^ a b c Bobzien 1999, p. 106
  26. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 109
  27. ^ Inwood 2003, p. 231
  28. ^ a b c Sellars 2006, p. 60
  29. ^ a b c Bobzien 1999, p. 129
  30. ^ Bobzien 1999, pp. 109–111
  31. ^ a b Sellars 2006, p. 59
  32. ^ a b Adamson 2015, p. 136
  33. ^ a b c d Bobzien, Susanne. "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  34. ^ Adamson 2015, p. 138
  35. ^ a b Adamson 2015, p. 58
  36. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 120
  37. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 118
  38. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 113
  39. ^ a b c Bobzien 1999, p. 121
  40. ^ a b Bobzien 1996, p. 881
  41. ^ Asmus & Restall2012, p. 21
  42. ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 128
  43. ^ a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 87
  44. ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 521
  45. ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 522
  46. ^ a b Barnes 1997, p. 82
  47. ^ Barnes 1997, p. 83
  48. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 122
  49. ^ Inwood 2003, p. 232
  50. ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 525
  51. ^ Asmus & Restall 2012, p. 20
  52. ^ a b c d Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 526
  53. ^ a b Nussbaum 2009, p. 349
  54. ^ Long 2001, p. 95
  55. ^ Hadot 2002, p. 135
  56. ^ Long 2001, p. 102
  57. ^ Nussbaum 2009, pp. 348–9
  58. ^ a b Long 2001, p. 92 citing Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 46f.
  59. ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 113
  60. ^ a b Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 177
  61. ^ Sharples 2003, p. 156
  62. ^ a b Hurley 2011, p. 6
  63. ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 403 quoting Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.
  64. ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 403
  65. ^ a b c d O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 397
  66. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 124
  67. ^ Bonevac & Dever 2012, p. 181
  68. ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, pp. 96–7

References[edit]

  • Adamson, Peter (2015), Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3
  • Asmus, Conrad; Restall, Greg (2012), "A History of the Consequence Relations", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Woods, John, Handbook of the History of Logic, 2, Elsevier, ISBN 978-0-444-52937-4
  • Barnes, Johnathan (1997), Logic and the Imperial Stoa, Brill, ISBN 90-04-10828-9
  • Barnes, Johnathan (1999), "Logic: The Peripatetics", in Algra, Keimpe, The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-25028-5
  • Bobzien, Susanne (1996), "Logic", in Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony, The Oxford Classical Dictionary, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-1986-6172-6
  • Bobzien, Susanne (1999), "Logic: The Stoics", in Algra, Keimpe, The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-25028-5
  • Bonevac, Daniel; Dever, Josh (2012), "A History of the Connectives", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Woods, John, Handbook of the History of Logic, 2, Elsevier, ISBN 978-0-444-52937-4
  • Everson, Stephen (1994), Companions to Ancient Thought 3: Language, Cambridge University Press
  • Hadot, Pierre (2002), What is Ancient Philosophy?, Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-00733-6
  • Hurley, Patrick J. (2011), A Concise Introduction to Logic, Wadsworth, ISBN 978-0-8400-3417-5
  • Ierodiakonou, Katerina (2006), "Stoicism", in Wilson, Nigel, Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece, Psychology Press, ISBN 978-0-4158-7396-3
  • Ierodiakonou, Katerina (2009), "Stoic Logic", in Gill, Mary Louise; Pellegrin, Pierre, A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Wiley-Blackwell, ISBN 978-1-4051-8834-0
  • Inwood, Brad (2003), "Stoicism", in Furley, David, Routledge History of Philosophy Volume II: Aristotle to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 978-0-4153-0874-8
  • Johansen, Karsten Friis; Rosenmeier, Henrik (1998), A History of Ancient Philosophy: From the Beginnings to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 0-415-12738-6
  • Kenny, Anthony (2006), Ancient Philosophy, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-875272-1
  • Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1962), The Development of Logic, Clarendon Press
  • Long, A. A. (2001), "Dialectic and the Stoic Sage", Stoic Studies, University of California Press, ISBN 0-520-22974-6
  • Nussbaum, Martha C. (2009), The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics, Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0-691-14131-2
  • O'Toole, Robert R.; Jennings, Raymond E. (2004), "The Megarians and the Stoics", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Woods, John, Handbook of the History of Logic, 1, Elsevier, ISBN 0-444-51596-8
  • Sellars, John (2006), Ancient Philosophies: Stoicism, Acumen, ISBN 978-1-84465-053-8
  • Shenefelt, Michael; White, Heidi (2013), If A, Then B: How Logic Shaped the World, Columbia University Press, ISBN 0-231-53519-8
  • Sharples, Robert W. (2003), "The Peripatetic School", in Furley, David, Routledge History of Philosophy Volume II: Aristotle to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 978-0-4153-0874-8
  • Zeller, Eduard (1880), The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Longmans, Green, and Co.

External links[edit]